Preprint
Review

Have I Been Touched? Subjective and Objective Aspects of Tactile Awareness

Submitted:

05 June 2024

Posted:

10 June 2024

You are already at the latest version

A peer-reviewed article of this preprint also exists.

Abstract
Somatosensory tactile experience is a key aspect of our interaction with the environment. It is involved in object manipulation, in the planning and control of actions and, in its affective components, in the relationships with other individuals. It is also a foundational component of body awareness. An intriguing aspect of sensory perception in general and tactile perception in particular is the way in which stimulation comes to consciousness. Indeed, although being aware of something seems a rather self-evident and monolithic aspect of our mental states, sensory awareness may be in fact modulated by many different processes that impact on the mere stimulation of the skin, including the way in which we perceive our bodies as belonging to us. In this review, we first took into consideration the pathological conditions of absence of phenomenal experience of touch, in the presence of implicit processing, as initial models for understanding the neural bases of conscious tactile experience. Subsequently, we discussed cases of tactile illusions both in normal subjects and in brain-damaged patients which help to understand which high order processes impact tactile awareness. Finally, we discussed the observations reported in the review in light of some influential models of touch and body representation.
Keywords: 
;  ;  ;  ;  ;  ;  ;  ;  

1. Introduction

Tactile processing is a fundamental element of human perception because, intervening in many cognitive processes, helps individuals to construct a consistent representation of the external world and a coherent experience of the sense of self. Indeed, it enables us to cope with the environment, signalling the contact with objects in space, and properly recognize (when vision is obstructed or prevented) the objects toward which our voluntary actions are directed (haptic object recognition) [1]. Moreover, touch sensation is fundamental to perceive the spatial limits and metrics of personal and peripersonal space (e. g. [2,3,4,5,6]) playing a key role in the recognition of our body as belonging to us, thus distinguishing it from others’ bodies (body ownership, see below and e.g. [7,8,9,10]). Related to the perception of one's own body and the bodies of others, touch can also assume an affective meaning that can convey to people a sense of pleasure and closeness (affective touch [11]). As pointed out by De Haan and Dijkerman [12] in their seminal paper on touch circuits, recent studies suggest that different, somehow distributed and, most importantly, partially overlapping networks are involved in touch perception based on the specific task to be accomplished. This implies that the network underlying both primary processing and more cognitive tasks are less segregated than originally suggested. As a consequence the model proposed by De Haan and Dijkerman took into account all possible components and interactions between the circuits where tactile stimuli are in different ways involved. In this paper, instead, we considered how awareness of a simple tactile stimulus given on the skin is constructed, focusing both on the subjective experience of touch when a stimulus is applied or impacts on the subject’s body and on the objective data that can verify the subject’s report. Indeed, one of the most intriguing questions posed by neuroscience is how external stimuli come to be experienced as conscious and therefore what mechanisms and brain circuits are responsible for sensory awareness [13,14]. It is therefore important to clarify that two aspects of consciousness will be considered here. The first is based on subjective reports (first person perspective), related to the phenomenal experience reported by the subject upon the occurrence of certain events. It has long been debated whether subjective reports can be accepted as data in scientific discourse, since the introspection that generates them is often considered aleatory and not objectively verifiable. However, many authors have criticized this prejudice because, while recognizing the methodological difficulty of considering the experience reported by the subjects, they can open an important window into the mechanisms of consciousness [15,16,17,18,19]. The second is based on objective data (third-person perspective) about the conscious experience of touch, to rule out the possibility of subjective reports being the result of mere confabulation. In other words, in this review it will be seen how the subjective reports related to phenomenal experience of touch can be a starting point for understanding tactile awareness, and how they can lead to the formulation of hypotheses that can be objectively tested by behavioural experiments or by relating the subjects’ phenomenal experiences to physiological responses and anatomical data. So the first question posed by this review is whether it is possible in the current state of knowledge to indicate the physiological conditions and neural basis of tactile consciousness.
In everyday life, the subjective experience of touch is usually perceived as directly contingent on the external events that generated it, because of the usual correspondence between the actual presence (or absence) of a stimulus, and the feeling (or absence of feeling) of being touched. There are, however, counterintuitive conditions where the phenomenal experience does not correspond to the actual stimulation. To this respect we shall first review clinical conditions in which the processing of stimuli that do not enter consciousness can nonetheless guide patient’s behaviour in the attempt to establish whether implicit and explicit processing of stimuli may follow different anatomo-physiological pathways. Then we shall discuss some abnormal phenomenal experience of touch in the absence of neurological damage and illusory experiences of touch in brain-damaged patients where subjects may feel a touch on their body when in fact no stimulation has been given and, conversely, have no tactile experience despite the presence of stimulation. With reference to the correspondence between stimulation and tactile experience reported by subjects in the different experiments, we will define as ‘veridical’ the condition in which the subjective report corresponds to the presence/absence of a sensory event and ‘non-veridical’ when it does not. Comparison of veridical and non-veridical touch perceptions and the conditions that determine them can unveil what processes, in addition to primary sensory analyses, modulate touch parameters regardless of the existence of true stimulation. This may allow us to unveil what are the necessary and sufficient conditions for tactile awareness to be generated under different conditions. It must also be kept in mind that touch, and more generally somatosensory experiences, have a special feature that other sensations do not have, that is the close relationship to body perception. Indeed, there is a two-way relationship between the subjective experience of touch (the feeling that a touch stimulus is given on my body) and the feeling of body ownership (i.e. the feeling that this body belongs to me). In Serino and Haggard words ‘the receptor organ for touch, the skin, also forms the surface of the physical body’ [20]. Consequently, situations in both normal subjects and brain-injured patients, where the close bottom up and top down relationship between touch and body affects one another, will also be considered. With this respect we will refer to models of body representation proposed by Tsakiris and Haggard [9], Serino and Haggard [20] and Gallace and Spence [14] which involve both top-down and bottom-up processes in the construction of body representation, and to a revision of these models recently proposed by us [21]. The aim of that part of the review is to show how the awareness of a simple touch is not simply anchored to the receptors on the skin that have been activated by the stimulation but also on how we experience our body.

2. Processing without awareness in the tactile domain.

It is worth mentioning that in neuroscience and neurology, one of the earliest cases of processing without awareness was that of blindsight where it was shown that visual stimuli can be processed either in a complete absence of visual experience (type 1 blindsight), or with a subjective feeling of experience without precise sensory connotation (type 2 blindsight) (see below). Many studies have been conducted over the years that have addressed behavioural as well as anatomical and physiological question on the mechanisms involved in the phenomenon of the absence of conscious vision, in the presence of stimulus processing (for a recent review see [22,23]). Blindsight is, therefore, a good reference model, both clinically and theoretically. Despite the diversity and peculiarities inherent in each sensory modality, it is reasonable to think that sensory experience is constructed through similar, although domain specific, mechanisms. We will therefore briefly recall here some aspects of blindsight that seem to us to be crucial for the understanding of the phenomenal experience of sensory events in general, and of tactile events in particular.
First described in the mid-1970s by Poppel and colleagues [24] and Weiskrantz and colleagues [25], blindsight is a condition where individuals, after a damage to the primary visual cortex that causes a blindness in the opposite visual field, can respond to certain aspects of visual stimuli presented in the blind field without having any actual phenomenal experience of them. For instance, if forced to make a guess on the location or direction of a visual event, blindsight patients are able to point toward the stimulus location or to correctly indicate in which direction the stimulus moves, despite claiming that they have not seen anything [26]. The presence of correct responses in absence of phenomenal experience, in addition to undermining some commonsense idea on consciousness (e.g. ‘If I don't see something I can't act on it’, see [27]), raises two main questions: first what are the mechanisms responsible for full awareness and, second, what are the mechanisms underlying processing without awareness. The possibility that consciousness is a threshold phenomenon, that occurs when there is a sufficient amount of neural activation, would predict the presence in blindsight subjects of residual brain tissue in V1 that would ensure enough activity for implicit but not explicit awareness. This hypothesis was, however, discarded because the blindsight phenomenon can be observed even in the total absence of cortical tissue as in the case of hemispherectomies [28]. An alternative hypothesis is that there may be dedicated pathways for explicit and implicit aspects of consciousness, suggesting for blindsight the existence of alternative visual route outside V1 that enable processing of visual stimuli (or at least of some of its prerogative) even in the absence of conscious perception. Weiskrantz and coworkers [29] found that it was possible in the same patient, by modulating certain stimulus parameters, to switch from type 1 blindsight, characterized by a total absence of visual experience, to type 2 blindsight, where patients report feeling that something has happened in the visual field. This observation inspired the study of brain activities in the different 'aware' and 'unaware' modes, which showed a shift in the pattern of activity from neocortex in the aware mode, to subcortical structures in the unaware mode. In particular, it was found that in the modes characterized by some form of awareness (type 2 blindsight and normal vision of the opposite hemifield) peristriate and prefrontal areas (in particular area 46) were activated, while in the unaware modes the main structure involved was the superior colliculus [30]. These results were later confirmed in a study by Tamietto and colleagues [31]. The anatomical results, especially the activation of prefrontal cortex in the aware mode, led many authors to claim that V1 may be necessary but not sufficient for explicit knowledge of visual sensory events. The blindsight phenomenon, in addition to indicating the possibility of processing without awareness, is also an example of false belief (the claim of not seeing anything despite the ability to respond to some characteristics of the stimulus) not due to a mere verbal confabulation, but to the activation of specific brain areas dedicated to implicit, but not explicit processing.
Reconnecting with the sense of touch, Paillard and coworkers [32] reported the first case of dissociation between explicit and implicit touch processing in a patient who, following a left hemisphere stroke that had produced parietal lobe ischemia, had developed complete anaesthesia of the contralateral body. Despite the complete inability to feel tactile stimuli even after consistent pressure on the skin, the patient was able to localize stimuli that she did not experience. This symptomatology resembles that of blindsight, and in fact the authors suggested the term 'blindtouch'. Even the patient's comments were similar to those of patients with blindsight. For example on one occasion she said: ‘But I don't understand that! You put something here. I don't feel anything and yet I go there with my finger. How does that happen?’. The anatomical description of the lesion was based only on CT images, but certainly the primary sensory cortex (S1) had been severely affected by the stroke. Therefore, although the possibility of residual islands of tissue could not be completely discarded (as in blindsight), the deep anaesthesia developed after the lesion suggested complete damage to S1. Having only the lesional data available, it is difficult to say in this case which cortical or subcortical areas are responsible for processing without awareness. The authors pointed to the possibility that either a supplementary sensory area or subcortical structure could be responsible for the implicit processing of tactile signal. A similar dissociation between unawareness of the stimulus and ability to indicate the stimulus location on the skin was also reported by Rossetti and colleagues [33]. They, however, found that their patient, although able to indicate the locus of the stimulation with a motor act, was not able to name the part of the body that was touched. Their conclusion was that their patient, in absence of stimulus awareness, was able to indicate its position on the skin by relying on a system that encodes how a movement should be done (how system), without constructing a more abstract representation of the location of the touch (where system). In their patient, structural brain damage was localized to the ventrolateral and ventroposterolateral nuclei of the thalamus. Functional studies on the same patient indicated hypometabolism not only in the damaged subcortical areas, but also in the frontoparietal cortices, particularly S1, consistent with a thalamocortical diaschisis. In any case we can conclude that the deafferentation of S1, due to the structural lesion, is again associated with the lack of phenomenal experience of touch. Regarding the implicit processing of the tactile stimulus, the authors proposed the somatic ipsilateral pathways as the substrate for the localization task, which potentially support sensitivity in hemispherectomized patients. Crucially, a similar ‘blindtouch’ has been obtained in healthy subjects using a TMS procedure to affect the functioning of S1 [34]. They found that despite transient loss of tactile awareness during TMS stimulation, subjects correctly localised the locus of stimulation although claiming not to feel the touches. All these data point to S1 as a necessary component of tactile awareness.
Another interesting model for the study of sensory awareness is that of the extinction phenomenon, where brain-damaged patients, although perfectly able to detect single stimulations, do not report the contralesional stimuli when presented simultaneously with ipsilesional ones. In other words, when two stimuli are simultaneously presented (double simultaneous stimulation, DSS), the one that should be processed by the lesioned hemisphere fades from awareness. For instance, in the visual domain, where most studies on extinction has been carried out, a stimulus presented on the contralesional visual field is not detected if another stimulus is presented in the ipsilesional visual field. This phenomenon is very frequent in right parietal patients. Many fMRI studies in these patients have shown that, when left visual events are extinguished during DSS, activations of the right striate and extrastriate visual cortices are still present although at a lower level with respect to the activations observed in single stimulation trials where stimuli are fully perceived (e.g. [35,36]). This may suggest that the residual processing might underlie some unconscious elaboration of extinguished contralesional visual stimuli. However both behavioural and fMRI studies did not directly investigate whether the patients had implicit processing and what areas activate when subjects, although not seeing anything, gave correct responses regarding the unseen stimulus. We only know that a residual activation of V1 was observed in extinguished trials. Another important observation is related to the fact that in trials where extinction was not present, i.e. the patients were aware of both stimuli, an additional activation in V1 was observed, thus confirming its fundamental role in giving rise to conscious percepts. Interestingly, Driver and colleagues [37] found that in conscious trials also prefrontal cortex was active, as in blindsight patients in the ‘aware’ mode. However, that unconscious visual processing can be present in patients with visual extinction has been demonstrated years ago by Volpe and colleagues for line drawing of objects presented one to the left and one to the right of a fixation cross. They showed that patients could judge whether the two objects were the same or different despite the fact that they were not aware of the presence of the contralesional stimuli. Berti and coworkers [38] even demonstrated that correct same/different judgements were not limited to simple line-drawings of two identical objects but extended to photograph of real different objects belonging to the same category and sharing the same name (e.g. a photograph of two different exemplar of a camera), thus showing a high level of analysis for unconscious visual events.
Extinction has been studied also, although more rarely, in the tactile domain. A seminal paper regarding the relation and anatomical correlate of tactile extinction and conscious touch perception is that of Sarri and colleagues [39]. They studied a patient with crossmodal tactile extinction in which a visual stimulus extinguished a tactile stimulus delivered on the contralesional side of the body . The patients presented an interesting pattern of awareness/unawareness responses with respect to the tactile stimulation because she showed crossmodal extinction of left touch on approximately half of DSS trials while being aware of left touch on the other half. Thus it was possible to study the brain activation in the aware/unaware condition in the same patient. The authors found, similar to the visual extinction situations, that when the tactile stimulus in DSS was extinguished, there was still residual (but less than in the tactile stimulation-only conditions) activation of S1. In those DSS trials where the patient was instead aware of the tactile stimulus, there was additional activation of S1, together with similar activation of prefrontal areas as observed in previous studies in other sensory modalities. These results suggest that for a full aware experience not only primary sensory cortices are needed but also anterior areas related to more abstract and general content of awareness (see discussion). It must be pointed out that in Sarri and colleagues’ study, implicit processing was not directly tested or observed, but only hypothesized based on the persistence of a certain level of parietal activation in the unaware conditions. Finally, it is interesting to note that implicit processing of extinguished stimuli has also been demonstrated in tactile extinction [40]. Berti and coworkers [41] found that unconscious processing of somatosensory stimuli can reach the categorical level, as in visual extinction. Indeed, their patient was able to give same/different correct responses in DSS trials, when she had no idea what the object presented to the contralesional hand was, even when stimuli, although sharing the name, were completely different exemplars of the same object. Note that in this patient extinction was always present on the contralesional hand even when it was positioned in the right space, suggesting that it was anchored to a body centered frame of reference, typical of the primary sensory areas. However, and somehow surprisingly, the detection of tactile stimuli presented to the healthy, ipsilesional, hand decreased when the good hand was positioned in the left space, indicating also an influence of some extrapersonal frame of reference in modulating tactile perception.
In summary these findings showed that: a) there is the possibility, of implicit processing of tactile information that do not reach awareness, as in the visual domain. We know that implicit processing in blindsight depends on the spared functioning of different pathways than the explicit processing, in particular the retino-collicular pathway. This does not exclude the possibility that, in other domains, as in the tactile system, residual activations of primary cortices underlie other forms of unconscious perception (see Sarri and colleagues suggestion [39]). b) tactile sensation can be affected by the space where the limb receive the stimulation. Indeed, although in the Berti and coworkers’ experiment tactile extinction was consistently present also when the affected hand was moved in the good space, tactile perception of the unaffected hand, placed in the contralesional space was somehow diminished, despite the fact that the sensory circuits of this hand, and in particular S1, were completely normal (not affected by any brain damage) [42]. c) The normal functioning of the V1 and S1 are necessary, but, perhaps, not sufficient for a full aware experience. Indeed S1 can be unaffected in extinction patients, and the patients may nonetheless be unaware of the tactile stimulus. We may infer that for a full aware experience other areas are involved, as suggested by the studies on blindsight in the visual domain (see discussion section). The involvement of prefrontal cortex might play a crucial role for the emergence of sensory consciousness.

3. Illusory experience of touch in healthy subjects

3.1. Tactile illusions

Illusion phenomena elicited in the tactile domain are one of the most fascinating examples of how our sense of touch can be deceived, leading to non-veridical tactile experiences. Of particular interest is the phenomenon of people that believe they have been touched when no actual tactile stimulation has been delivered. For example, in the ‘funneling illusion’ [22] two tactile stimuli applied on the skin are perceived in a single un-stimulated skin site, localized at a central position with respect to the two stimulated areas. Chen and colleagues [23] investigated the brain correlates of the funneling illusion in the monkey brain, showing that the simultaneous stimulation of two fingers resulted in a single focal cortical activation located between the regions corresponding to the individual fingertip activations in the primary somatosensory cortex area 3b. This indicates that, even in the absence of a tactile stimulus at the funneled site, the cortical response was comparable to that of an actual single-digit stimulation. Another example of this phenomenon is the ‘cutaneous rabbit illusion’ [24]. In this paradigm, a series of rapid taps are delivered sequentially along the skin of a participant, typically on the arm at two or more skin locations. After the tactile stimuli have been delivered, participants often perceive the sensation of a continuous hopping or ‘rabbit-like’ motion moving along the skin between the actual points of contact. Note that, for the illusion to occur, stimuli must be presented to adjacent regions of the skin (i.e., the illusion does not occur if stimuli are presented from the hand to the foot). This means that the cutaneous rabbit illusion might be constrained by the somatotopic organization of the somatosensory cortex [25], suggesting that this illusion is related to early stages of information processing [26]. The neural mechanisms behind this illusion have been investigated by Blankenburg and colleagues [27], who recorded brain activity of participants during the perception of the illusion across the arm. What they found is that when participants experienced the illusion, there was significant activation in S1 at the location corresponding to the perceived, but not physically stimulated, intermediate points along the arm. This activation was also comparable in magnitude to that produced by actual tactile stimulation at those intermediate locations. Furthermore, researchers found activity in premotor and prefrontal regions, which may indicate an important role of these structures in the top-down modulation of somatosensory information processing in S1 during illusory (non-veridical) touch experiences. These striking data that show in healthy individual that it is possible to feel in a location that is different from the one that has been stimulated, again suggest a fundamental role of S1 in the generation of conscious awareness even when it is non-veridical.

3.2. Rubber hand illusion

Particularly interesting for understanding the process that give rise to tactile awareness are the illusions where tactile experience is modulated through a multisensory stimulations that alters the way in which we perceive our body, as in the Rubber Hand Illusion (RHI) [28]. The RHI phenomenon is typically induced by having a participant place one hand out of sight (usually hidden behind a screen) while a fake rubber hand is placed in view, positioned in a congruent manner to the common location of the participant’s real hand. The experimenter then synchronously strokes both the hidden real hand and the visible fake rubber hand with brushes. After a short period of synchronous stimulation, many participants begin to feel as if the rubber hand is part of their own body and report the sensation of touch (the one given on the own hidden hand) on the rubber hand, where they see the stimulation. This phenomenon can be measured subjectively, by asking participants to give a rating of how much they feel the rubber hand as if it was their own hand, or quantitatively, by measuring the drift of the perceived position of the participant hand towards the rubber hand. During the initial period of stimulation there is an obvious bottom-up multisensory conflict between touch and proprioception (which coincide) and vision (which is in contrast to the other two modalities). The conflict is solved by recalibrating proprioception to the position where the subject sees touching the rubber hand. This would lead to a change in body references and to the self-attribution of the rubber hand that is embodied in the mental representation of the participant’s own body. However, for the illusion to occur, some constrains must be met: the fake hand must resemble a normal hand in size and shape (e.g. an elongated stick does not work), the fake and real hands must be of the same identity (i.e., both right or left hands), the fake hand must be positioned in near space internally with respect to the real hand and in egocentric perspective (the rubber hand in allocentric perspective does not elicited the illusion) [9,29]. These constraints are obviously related to an acquired body representation, related to previous knowledge of the appearance of bodies, a sort of pre-existing body representation, which in a top-down manner limits what can be considered part of a body [9]. Therefore, both bottom-up and top-down processes are needed for the illusion to occur (see also [30]). Note that self-attribution of the fake hand as part of the own body leads to localization of touch on the rubber hand, causing the counterintuitive effects of feeling on a fake hand. Interestingly, some studies have indicated that the incorporation of the rubber hand corresponds at an implicit level to a momentary disownership of one's real hand. For example, Zeller and colleagues [31] showed how tactile acuity (i.e., the ability to discriminate and perceive tactile stimuli) of the hand subjected to the illusion is significantly reduced, as well as the amplitude of the somatosensory potentials evoked by a tactile stimulus (see also [32] for a similar results in the motor domain). Therefore, the rubber hand illusion suggests how the phenomenal experience of touch is not exclusively dependent on direct sensory input but can be the result of a complex integration between multisensory stimulation and the sense of body ownership.
Many studies tried to identify the areas and circuits involved in the self-attribution of rubber hand. According to some authors [33], recalibration of proprioception to the position where tactile stimulation is seen involves activation of frontoparietal circuits that include the intraparietal cortex, the supplementary motor area and the cerebellum. However, when the illusion is achieved, and tactile and somatosensory perception needs to be integrated with vision, the area that becomes active is in the premotor cortex, where bimodal visuotactile neurons are ideal candidates for the integration of visual and somatosensory signals [34,35]. Interestingly, an fMRI study showed that in participants that non-veridically perceived their arm as longer when an elongated rubber hand was used, an expansion of the area dedicated to the tactile representation of the arm was observed in S1 [36].
Taken together, these findings suggest that vision may affect tactile perception in different ways. In the case of RHI, vision wins over proprioception during multisensory stimulation by dragging tactile awareness from one's own limb to the rubber hand. Furthermore, the data on RHI indicates that the subjective tactile experience involves, beyond the activation of S1, higher order processing regions involved in the construction of body ownership.

3.3. Mirror box illusion and phantom sensation in healthy individuals

The mirror box illusion (MBI) was initially developed by Ramachandran and colleagues as a therapeutic tool intended to treat phantom limb pain experienced by amputees (a condition in which amputee patients can perceive pain in a limb that is no longer there). In this illusion, a mirror is placed perpendicular to the trunk midline of the patient’s body (with one limb on each side of the mirror) creating the illusion that the reflected limb is actually the opposite missing limb. This visual illusion can lead to significant changes in the patient’s body perception, including relief from phantom limb pain, and alterations in perceived tactile sensations [37]. The fundamental theory behind the MBI is that, under certain circumstances, a visual feedback that creates the illusion that a missing limb is intact and moving can alter the brain’s mechanisms involved in body perception [38]. In one study, [39] showed that in amputees it was possible to induce not only kinesthetic sensations, but even an intermanual referral of touch. They asked a patient with a right limb amputation to look into the mirror at the reflection of his left hand so that the reflection was superimposed on the felt position of the right phantom limb. When the experimenter stroked individual fingers on the left hand, the patients reported a touch sensation in the exact symmetric location on his right phantom limb. This finding suggests that the persistence of brain maps dedicated to tactile processing and body representation in amputees may underlie the illusion created by the mirror as in healthy individuals (see below), despite the absence of the corresponding limb.
In later studies, the MBI was used to investigate various aspects of visuo-tactile integration also in individuals with intact limbs. In these participants, the MBI induces, as in the amputees, the feeling that one of the own limbs reflected in the mirror is actually the other limb hidden behind the mirror, and it has been widely used to induce visual/proprioceptive conflicts. In one particular example, Ro and colleagues [40] asked participants to look at the reflection of their right hand being brushed by the experimenter. In such conditions, the visual information (i.e., the mirror reflection of their right hand being touched) made it seem like their left hand was being touched instead. After a short time, many participants reported the feeling of being touched on the left real hand, while the tactile information was only delivered on the right hand.. These data first show how the possible “embodiment” of the reflected hand can have an effect on tactile awareness. Moreover, the authors applied after the MBI procedure a near-threshold electrical pulses delivered to the middle finger of the hand that was not actually stimulated during the MBI. It must be noted that, usually, near-threshold electrical stimulations increase sensitivity when a real stimulation is previously delivered on the skin. Accordingly, they found that the stimuli delivered at threshold-level on the real left hand that underwent the illusion during the MBI was perceived more easily following exposure to the mirror, as if it was really stimulated. Interestingly, inhibiting the activity of the posterior parietal lobule with a TMS procedure, abolished the 'facilitation' effect. These data demonstrated that the illusion of being touched on one hand when in fact stimulation is given on the other hand has effects on the sensory parameters of the hand that did not receive any tactile stimuli, showing also in the domain of this experiment, that the phenomenal non-veridical experience of touch has consequences on veridical touch perception. Furthermore the fact that TMS on parietal areas inhibits the facilitation induced by the MBI, not only show that these areas are involved in touch modulation, but that this effect is also verifiable for non-veridical tactile experiences.
The possible mechanisms behind the MBI are mainly ascribed to the mismatch between vision, touch, and proprioception [28,41]. As in RHI, the MBI reveals the brain's tendency to rely more heavily on visual information when there are conflicting sensory inputs [42]. Different studies explored the neural correlates of the illusory touch in the MBI. Interestingly it was found (e.g. [43]) that stimulating the right hand (reflected in the mirror) created a medial shift in the cortical representation of that hand, that is closer to the cortical representation of the left-hand, showing how S1 topography can adjust to accommodate for the “embodied limb”. These data show how tactile awareness is modulated by multisensory stimulations possibly integrated at the cortical level, but also by subjects' perception (veridical or not) of their own bodies. Moreover, the shift of the stimulated hand representation to the non-stimulated hand in S1 indicates that a change in tactile awareness is accompanied by altered activity in the primary sensory cortices.

3.4. Synchiric errors

Recently, we reported a new phenomenon in the domain of illusory tactile experiences in healthy subjects using the MBI paradigm [44]. We delivered symmetrical and asymmetrical stimulations on the dorsum of the hands of participants while their left-hand was out of sight (hidden behind the mirror) and the right hand was reflected in the mirror so that it resembled the own left hand. In this setup, during asymmetrical simultaneous stimulation of the two hands, participants not only saw the right hand reflected in the mirror as if it was the left hand, but also saw it being touched by the stimuli given to the real right hand. This implied that, when the right hand was touched in one position, and the hidden left hand received the touch on a different position, subjects saw in the hand reflected in the mirror a touch that was ‘symmetrical’ to that given on the real right hand. What we found is that, during asymmetrical stimulations, participants erroneously reported the touch on the left hidden hand as symmetrical to the stimulation on the right hand. We called this phenomenon “synchiric error” because it resembles synchiria [45,46], a phenomenon in which patients describe the feeling of being touched on two symmetrical sides of the body when only one side is stimulated. We ascribed this phenomenon to a combination of both bottom-up and top-down processes. The conflicting multisensory integration induced by our setup, that is, the feeling of touch on the left-hand while seeing the touch on the right reflected hand (bottom-up sensory processing) together with a possible embodiment of the reflected right hand as the own left hand (top-down modulation of body ownership) might have induced the non-veridical sensory experience on the left hidden hand [44], coherently with previous finding by Ro and colleagues [40].

4. Phantom touch in brain-damaged patients.

4.1. Synchiric extinction

Tactile perception in post stroke patients is typically assessed by administering tactile stimuli to the patients’ hands, either unilaterally or bilaterally, and asking them to say yes when they feel the touch. In some occasion they are also asked to indicate the locus of stimulation. Note that, usually, in the clinical testing of tactile perception bilateral stimuli are delivered in symmetrical positions on the two hands. This procedure helps to evaluate errors in reporting contralesional single stimuli, as in primary somatosensory deficits or neglect [47], but also the inability to detect contralesional touches during simultaneous bilateral stimulation, as in tactile extinction [48]. Additionally, this procedure is also used to identify phenomena such as synchiria [45], where patients experience bilateral tactile sensations from unilateral stimulation, and allochiria, where patients mislocalize contralesional stimuli to the ipsilesional side of the body [49]. However, we found that this standard procedure, does not capture extinction errors when the patient who may present extinction with double symmetric stimulation, still reports two stimuli because the perception of the stimulus on the healthy side induces a phantom feeling of touch on the affected side (sinchiric errors). That is, since the stimuli are given symmetrically the synchiric error is masked. We discovered this phenomenon in a study where stroke patients who apparently did not show any sign of tactile deficits under standard evaluation of touch showed extinction on the contralesional side using a new procedure called Tactile Quadrant Stimulation protocol (TQS) [50]. Following this procedure, we delivered tactile stimuli on one of the four quadrants of the patient’s hands. Single stimulations, symmetrical double stimulations, and in the crucial condition, asymmetrical double stimulation (ADS) of the hands were present. Patients had to report the side and position of the stimuli. Results showed that more than 50% of the patients, although correctly reporting a bilateral tactile sensation in ADS trials, indicated as the locus of stimulation, symmetrical positions on the two hands. In other words, for the contralesional hand, they claimed to feel touch on the quadrant (that was not actually stimulated) that corresponded to the one stimulated on the ipsilesional hand. We called this non-veridical tactile experience ‘synchiric extinction’ because it resembles synchiria but selectively arose after a possible extinction of the actual stimulus during ADS trials. The synchiric extinction phenomenon may reflect neuroplastic mechanisms triggered by the brain lesion, that unmask pathological bilateral touch representation following unilateral stimulation [51,52,53,54] that are normally inhibited in the healthy brain [46].

4.2. Touch and body illusion in brain-damaged patients

In the next section we shall discuss neuropsychological syndromes characterized by abnormalities in body perception and in the sense of body ownership where tactile awareness is impaired or affected in different ways. As pointed out in the introduction we can define the sense of body ownership as the conscious feeling of property over my body or in Tsakiris’s words [55], ‘the special perceptual status of one’s own body, which makes bodily sensations seem unique to oneself, that is, the feeling that ‘‘my body’’ belongs to me, and is ever present in my mental life’. A special point of interest in this definition for the discussion we are doing about touch is that body ownership makes body sensations unique to one’s self. This implies the exclusivity of the relationship between perception of an event on one's body and the property of that body. We have already seen how with particular procedures it is possible to undermine this relationship in healthy subjects. We shall see even more counterintuitive behaviours in brain-damaged patients in the next paragraphs. Regarding perceptions and representations of the body, in the classical literature, a distinction was usually made between the concepts of body schema and body image. Body image refers to conscious representations about visual features of the body and of its appearance, whereas body schema is a representation that, unconsciously, guides postural and motor processes in both action execution and perception of body in space [7,13,56,57,58]. Although there is now a tendency to use more complex definitions of the various high order components on which body ownership depends, we will still refer in some parts of our review to this distinction, considering it efficacious in capturing some phenomena observed in both healthy subjects and patients with brain injury.

4.3. Delusion of disowneship

One of the most surprising behaviors that can be observed after a focal brain injury is the explicit denial that a limb belongs to one's own body. This pathological condition often accompanied by the attribution of the limb to another person, is called Somatoparaphrenia (SPP) [59] and is interpreted as a sort of discorporation (disownership). A causal role for SPP has been attributed to a complete alteration of somatic sensitivities. Indeed, the association between somatosensory deficits and the denial of belonging is very frequent. In many cases of SPP an apparent total disturbance of sensation, and particularly of touch, seemed to afflict the patients. However, Moro and colleagues [60] found in two SPP patients that when the contralesional arm (the one affected by the disowership) was moved to the space unaffected by the lesion, the patients were able to report tactile stimulations, although SPP would continue to persist. Therefore, not only this observation would show that SPP is not caused by sensory deficits, but indicates that tactile awareness is modulated by the space where the patient’s arm is [60]. Interestingly, when the unaffected arm was moved into the contralesional affected space, some tactile stimuli were not perceived (see also [61]). Similarly, and even more striking is the behaviour of patient FB described by Bottini and colleagues [62]. The patient who, after a right hemisphere stroke, developed a complete paralysis contralateral to the brain damage, did not report, in the routine neurological exam, any tactile stimuli on her left arm. When the examiners brought the patient's attention to the affected hand, the patient claimed that that hand was not hers and that it belonged to her niece, showing a severe and persistent somatoparaphrenic behaviour. At this point, the patient was told that she would receive a touch either on her right or left hand or on her niece's hand. In the latter case, the examiners would again touch the left hand of the patient. The patient was asked to keep her eyes closed, and to say if and where she had been touched. Surprisingly, the tactile anaesthesia of the left hand, which was very consistent when the examiners were telling the patient that they were touching her hand (the one that was (discorporated), disappeared (i.e. the patient reported tactile stimuli correctly) when the examiners said they were touching the hand of the niece. Considering that the patient was performing the task with her eyes closed, the only factor influencing her responses was the belief (true or false) about the hand ownership, induced by the examiners’ information. It is clear that in patient FB the cortical areas deputed to the analysis of sensory stimuli had to be intact, given the patient's ability to correctly report the touch on her left hand when she believed it was her niece's hand being touched. As in Moro and colleagues’ study the aware experience of touch depended upon the believes related to the hand ownership that counterintuitively led the patients to feel stimuli on someone else's hand.
Finding a relationship between the non-veridical phenomenal experience reported by patients and objective, quantifiable data would allow us to grasp the neurological, not confabulatory, reality of the disownership phenomenon. For example, the existence of a relationship between the rejection of one's own hand and changes in some physiological indices would be fundamental to tie the delusion to the neural mechanisms that likely determine it. Many studies have shown that approaching to the body of a potentially painful stimulus (such as a needle or syringe) results in an increase in skin conductance (Skin Conductance Response, SCR). This is considered an ‘anticipatory’ response due to the existence of circuits dedicated to the detection of potentially "threatening" stimuli approaching to the body. These circuits would include the neural systems responsible for processing tactile and visual stimuli, signaling in advance possible harmful impacts on the body surface [34,35]. For the approaching stimulus to be considered dangerous to the body, the subjects undergoing the experiment must regard the threatened body part as belonging to themselves. Under this assumption, if a body part is no longer considered one’s own, then the threat should not result in an increase in SCR. Romano and coworkers [63] registered the SCR in five patients with SPP, during the presentation of "painful" stimuli approaching to the right (healthy) hand or the left (affected by the illusion of discorporation) hand and found that while for the right hand the SCR increased as expected (the right hand is recognized as own), for the left hand no anticipation response was found. This result is extremely indicative of the fact that the hand that is discorporated in the SPP patient is not treated as the own hand by the neural systems in charge of body defense.
Another condition of relative disownership is one in which subjects, with no apparent brain injury and in the absence of psychiatric disorders, would like to amputate a limb. In this dramatic condition, termed xenomelia by Hilti and colleagues [64], but better known with the term Body Integrity Dysphoria (BID), the 'patients' claim that the physical appearance of their body (i.e., what their body really looks like) does not match the mental image they have of it. Some patients may say that they feel ‘over-complete’ (e.g. [65]) and claim that they would feel "normally" complete with three limbs, which suggests the presence of a distortion of the body image, somehow similar to that of SPP patients (for a discussion of these disownership conditions see also [21,66]). Particularly interesting for what we are discussing here is that some patients report the feeling that tactile stimulations are attenuated on the limb they would like to amputate, and the resulting impression is that the touched limb does not belong to them [67]. These subjective feelings could be explained by the fact that patients, wanting to get rid of the limb, try to ignore it. As a consequence of decreased attention, stimulations would be processed less effectively by the nervous system. Alternatively, the attenuated sensations could be due to less (or absent) representation of that limb in the brain. In this case, although the neural pathways for primary processing of tactile sensations are intact (recall that these patients have no obvious nerve pathway lesions), the lack of the mental image of the affected limb, with which to integrate them, would prevent the full experience of the stimulation. Romano and colleagues [68] conducted a study aimed at understanding whether there was a difference, in patients with BID, in SCR responses when the tactile stimulus (given with a small needle) actually touches the patients' skin (real stimulation) versus when the stimulus does not touches it (threat). The authors found that the SCR is increased when the stimuli touched the skin of the unwanted limb, while it was reduced when the stimuli did not touch it. In other words, in patients with BID, the decreased anticipatory response for the unwanted limb is similar to the response observed in SPP patients for the "discorporated" limb. In contrast, the response to actual limb stimulation was increased (see also [69]). The apparent contradiction between the increased response to actual stimulation and a decreased response to threat was explained by the authors as due to the key role played by attention in modulating SCR. Romano and collaborators have proposed that attention toward the unwanted limb is actually decreased, on the assumption that dislike towards the affected limb is such that it leads patients to ignore it as much as possible. The diminished response to threat is therefore due to the fact that one does not expect to be threatened on something that does not exist (or that one wish did not exist). But precisely because in BID the unwanted limb is treated as if it was not part of the own body, when it is actually touched there would be a kind of startle response that would increase the SCR to the actual stimulation. In the attempt to find the neural based of BID, Hilti and colleagues [64] conducted a structural studies on a group of BID patients compared to a group of healthy population. They found that in BID there was a reduction of cortical thickness and volume in the superior parietal lobule and a reduced cortical surface area of the inferior parietal lobule, of a small portion of the frontal lobe, of the primary somatosensory areas and of the cortex of the insula. More recently Saetta and coworkers [70] also showed that the S1 area, related to the to-be-removed leg, and the right superior parietal lobule were less functionally connected to the rest of the brain. Although these abnormalities are very limited and quantitatively minor with respect to the lesion observed in brain damaged patients, they nonetheless indicate the involvement of brain regions responsible for body representation and tactile elaboration. Interestingly, the study by Hilti and colleagues found that brain areas involved in the structural abnormalities in BID patients partially overlap with the areas that are damaged in SPP patients [71,72]) suggesting, therefore, a close link between the negative attitude towards an unwanted limb and the lesional pattern where patients overtly deny the limb’s ownership. It is worth noting that the brain abnormalities found in patients with BID may be the effect of underutilization, repeatedly documented in these patients, of the unwanted limb, and not the cause of the disorder. In any case, both behavioral and anatomical similarities between BID and SPP suggest that the structural abnormalities identified in the brain of these patients involve an alteration of complex circuits responsible for the integration of sensory information with body representation. In both BID and SPP patients, the partial or complete sense of disowenrship, possibly due to a sort of ‘amputation’ of the body image (congenital in BID, acquired after the stroke in brain-damaged patients, see also [21]), affect the way in which tactile sensation is experienced.

4.4. Delusion of ownership

We recently described a neuropsychological disorder, that could be considered the opposite of SPP, in which something similar to what happens in healthy subjects during the RHI occurs. Patients suffering from it incorporate limbs of other people (that, in this context, we call ‘alien’ limb) when these are presented in positions compatible with their own body. In accordance with what Tsakiris and Haggard (2005) described for the RHI, for the embodiment to occur the 'alien' limb must be in an egocentric position, internal to the patient’s own limb and of the same identity. We have called this disorder 'Pathological Embodiment' (PE) [21,73]. Usually these patients have a lesion in the right hemisphere, and therefore the affected part of the body is the left one, most often the left hand. In the typical assessment setting, where the patient with PE is seated with both hands resting on the table, the examiner, standing behind the patient, places his or her left arm between the patient's real left arm and trunk. At this point there are three arms on the table and the patient, without any multisensory stimulation maneuvers such as the one used to induce the rubber hand illusion, immediately recognizes as his/her own hand both the right own hand and examiner’s left hand. This does not happen when an alien right hand is positioned on the right (healthy) side where the patients do not have any ownership illusion. Note that this phenomenon is observed without the patients’ explicit refusal of the left own limb when the alien limb is not present. On the other hand, when the alien limb is present and is incorporated, only then do the patients deny that the limb affected by the lesion is their own, coherently with the general knowledge that a person cannot have three limbs (if an alien limb is incorporated then one must be discorporated). Another important constrain of this illusion of ownership is that the ‘alien’ limb must be a real one, as PE does not occur with fake hands. Of course the fundamental difference between RHI and PE is that while healthy individuals undergoing RHI know that the rubber hand is not theirs, patients with PE are convinced that the alien hand belongs to their body. As Frederique de Vignemont pointed out ‘something can be considered ‘incorporated’ if it is treated as a part of the own body’ [7]. Coherently with this hypothesis, we have shown in several studies that the examiner's alien hand is indeed treated like the patient’s own hand in several domains [74,75]. Here it is important to mention how tactile awareness is modulated in PE patients. In one study we asked patients to give a score relative to the perceived strength of stimulation on both hands (using a pinprick) [76]. The score ranged from 0 (‘I feel nothing) to 5 (‘I feel perfectly’). Patients were selected on the basis of having relatively intact touch sensation even on the contralesional hand, which thus acted as a control for the alien hand. We found that patients gave the same (high) scores when their own (healthy) right hand and alien left hand were stimulated under the conditions of embodiment described above. They also gave scores consistent with good touch perception on their own left hand when assessed in the absence of the alien hand. When the examiner's right hand, that corresponded to the patient’s healthy hand, was stimulated they felt absolutely nothing. Coherently with the subjective report of feeling on the alien hand, we found, using SCR, that the anticipatory response was identical, and increased with respect to the absence of stimulation, when the pinprick stimulation was presented on the own right hand and on the left alien hand, definitively showing that when the alien hand is incorporated it is treated as the own hand [77]. Somehow unexpected was the fact that when the stimulation was presented to the left hand in absence of the corresponding alien hand and therefore explicitly recognised by the patients as their own, no increase of the SCR was observed (as in SPP patients). We interpreted this result as indicating an implicit state of limb disownership for the contralesional hand, which in the presence of the alien hand is indeed not recognized as one's own. Thus, in the face of correct explicit ownership over the contralesional hand when alien hands are not present, the implicit SCRs suggest unconscious disownership. This could explain the tendency of these patients to incorporate alien hands when conditions for incorporation occur. In PE patients the brain injury has not completely damaged body representation because in the absence of alien hands their behaviour indicates good perception of body experiences at the explicit level. The lesional data, although showing damages of different cortical areas, did not show any specific cortex involved in PE group with respect to the control group of brain-damaged patients without PE [73]. Instead in the PE group, subcortical structures such as the corona radiate and the superior longitudinal fasciculus seem to be specifically damaged. This would imply a possible disconnection between the different brain areas devoted to the body representation, thus impairing a full coherent sense of body ownership. The results would not be a complete disruption of body image, but instead an instable and fragile body representation that, as just said, makes patients willing to accept as their own any limb that is in a compatible and congruent position for being part of their body. Going back to the veridical and non-veridical experience of touch in PE patients, these data show that the phenomenal experience of touch (still possible because these patients do not have damage to S1) is modulated by the feeling of ownership over the own and alien hands, whether veridical or illusory.

5. Discussion

The experience that we have of ourselves is characterized, under normal conditions, by an unquestionable feeling of unity and coherence. Therefore, in everyday life it is difficult to separate a single stream of consciousness from the whole of our conscious experiences. However it is possible, using specific experimental conditions together with the study of anomalous illusory situations to isolate one sensory experience from the others in order to study how conscious experience is constructed. In this review we set out to study how evidence in both healthy subjects and brain-damaged patients can provide useful insights into a specific domain of awareness that is tactile awareness. Touch is always present in our experience and, therefore, in our mental life, and is a stimulation that continuously affects our body, interacting with other senses and especially with the feeling of body ownership. In particular, touch begins on the skin, that is on the body, where different kinds of receptors convert physical stimuli into electrical signals through sensory transduction, generating receptor potentials that may trigger action potentials in primary afferent neurons. These neurons transmit sensory information to the central nervous system. They cross to the contralateral side before ascending through the medial lemniscus to the ventrolateral posterior (VLP) and ventromedial posterior (VMP) nuclei of the thalamus and from these nuclei to the primary somatosensory cortex (S1), located in the post-central cortex and to the secondary somatosensory cortex (S2) located more posteriorly in the parietal lobe [78]. Interestingly, the ventral and the lateral posterior thalamic nuclei also project to premotor and posterior parietal cortices. These pathways (in Serino and Haggard [20] model indicated as pathway 1; see also [14]) reach the cortex via subcortical structure in a manner analogous to other sensory modalities, particularly vision. Although Gallace and Spence [13,14] in their seminal papers pointed more to the dissimilarity between visual and tactile awareness, here we would like, instead, to emphasize similarities that, we are convinced, can help us drawing inferences about how tactile consciousness is constructed.

5.1. S1 is necessary but not sufficient for tactile awareness

First, also in tactile domain we can observe implicit processing of information, in absence of any sensory experience. We have seen that this can happen both in the complete absence of the main pathways for primary sensory processes (as in blind touch, where S1 is surely affected, like V1 in blindsight patients) and in conditions in which primary sensory cortex is spared (like in tactile extinction or in visual extinction where V1 and S1 are not affected). These observations suggest that both in vision and touch primary sensory cortices are necessary for tactile awareness (if they are destroyed, as in blindtouch and blindsight no awareness for the processed stimuli is still possible). It must be noted that the fact that S1 is intact in extinction does not mean that S1 is not involved in awareness. Indeed, patients are completely aware of stimuli when they are delivered in isolation, either to right or to the left limb. Unawareness in extinction occurs when the system is loaded by double simultaneous touches. In this case, the analysis of the touch that reaches the healthy and efficient cortex is facilitated (and then consciously reported) with respect to the one that would reach the lesioned hemisphere (which is neglected). Indeed, extinction can be considered a mild form of inattention or lack of spatial awareness, due to lesions to the posterior parietal lobe (see [79] for a similar explanation of unilateral neglect). Therefore, the unawareness of touch with spared primary somatosensory cortex, observed in extinction, suggests that S1, although necessary, is not sufficient to generate a conscious tactile experience. Other higher order brain areas must contribute to the emergence of a conscious experience of touch (see below). Returning to the role played by S1 in the processing of tactile stimuli, other data discussed in this review indicate its fundamental involvement in the emergence of awareness. For example, in tactile illusions, the perception of a stimulus referred to a point on the skin other than those actually stimulated (as in the funnelling illusion) is accompanied by plastic changes of neural response localized in the primary sensory area. In other words, the non-veridical tactile awareness that emerges, although not related to the activation of the skin receptors actually stimulated by touch, nevertheless depends on the activation of S1. Similarly in the cutaneous rabbit illusion, Blankenburg and colleagues [27] found an activation of S1 when subjects perceived the illusion at the location corresponding to the perceived, but not physically stimulated, intermediate points along the arm. Even more compelling is the evidence that the magnitude of activation observed during the illusion was comparable to that observed when the stimulus was effectively delivered at the intermediate location. Similarly, in the MBI when the tactile stimulation of the right reflected hand in the mirror causes to feel the reflected hand as the own left hand, Egsagaard and colleagues [43] showed a medial shift of the right hand representation in S1 toward the real hand that, although not really stimulated, feels the touch. Again a tactile awareness, even in a non-veridical condition, is accompanied by activation of S1. Finally, a finding that incontrovertibly points to the direct involvement of S1 in tactile consciousness is that inhibition of S1 with TMS results in a momentary blindtouch-like condition in normal subjects [80].
S1 is certainly not the only area involved in conscious tactile experience. Sensory information is transferred from S1 to S2, a parietal area that is connected to various circuits that influence the processing of S1 in a top-down manner [14]. The lesions that produce extinction are adjacent and sometimes correspond to these areas and we have just seen that in the presence of an intact S1, but with these parietal areas damaged, tactile awareness is suppressed. All these data point to the fact that the circuits involved in tactile consciousness are the same that are responsible for the processing of tactile information. That is consciousness seems not to be related to some superimposed amodal process that is common to all modalities. We proposed this view for motor awareness [14,81] where the area most damaged in anosognosia for hemiplegia (that is a disorder of awareness related to motor function) is the premotor area 6. However, in blindsight patients the (amodal) prefrontal area 46 has been found to be active in both the full aware mode and in the attenuated awareness in type 2 blindsight [82]. Interestingly, another area that we found to be selectively damaged in anosognosic patients is area 46. So while the emergence of a conscious sensory experience certainly requires the activities of the primary processing areas, other amodal areas could contribute to conscious processing. As for tactile processing, there are no studies that specifically evaluate the role of area 46 in tactile awareness. The picture that emerges, however, from studies conducted in other specific domains seems to suggest that different brain circuits are necessary but not sufficient to determine conscious experience, and that amodal areas such as area 46 may also contribute to these circuits. A possible hypothesis is that the reciprocal connections between primary and amodal areas guarantee the primary area a sufficient activation level for the emergence of awareness. This can be reached by back-projections from higher order areas to S1 and S2, including area 46. As Gallace and Spence pointed out: ‘We believe that a certain threshold level of activation in the circuit needs to be reached […] in order for awareness to be generated’. As blindsight studies pointed out, consciousness might not be a matter of threshold activation, but more of activity in specific circuits. However, the two hypotheses are not in contrast with each other and it is possible to assume that, even within a dedicated circuit, a certain threshold of activation is necessary to trigger the conscious experience.

5.2. Neural bases of processing without awareness

If the lack of tactile awareness in blindtouch is ascribed to the damage to S1, less clear is the neural basis of the processing without awareness which is nevertheless present. One possibility is that similar to blindsight there is a separate, dedicated circuit that supports non-conscious responses also in the tactile domain. In this regard, Gallace and Spence [14] suggest in their model pathways from the thalamus to the posterior parietal cortex and to premotor cortex that may sustain implciit processing. However, in their model these pathways seem not be segregated as the retino-colliculo-extrastriate pathway in the blindsight. In particular, they suggested a route that goes from the posterolateral thalamic nuclei to the many different secondary and amodal cortices, that are actually involved in many different spatial and cognitive processes. This can be surely a possibility, but it is not a complete segregated pathway. However, another interesting possibility has been proposed by Rossetti and colleagues [83]. In their patient with damage to the left ventrolateral and ventroposterior lateral nuclei of the thalamus, functional investigation also demonstrated important hypometabolism to the whole parietal cortex. Therefore alternative thalamocortical pathways cannot be considered in this case responsible for the processing without awareness. Interestingly, Rossetti and colleagues proposed that the unaware processing could be carried out by ipsilateral somatic pathways. This would imply a bilateral representation of touch, as many authors has already proposed even if in other clinical disturbances. One possibility is that the ipsilateral representation is not as strong and efficient as the contralesional one, causing an activation in the ipsilateral pathways that is sufficent for implicit processing but not for the explicit awareness. Note that Sarri and colleagues [84], have proposed for extinction that the survival of primary sensory cortex may sustain the implcit processing. However, in their study they did not test the presence of implicit processing, therefore no conclusion can be drawn in this repsect. As for the other studies on sensory extinction with spared implicit processing the hypothesis is that the brain damage affect spatial awareness, while leaving intact or still working, but at a lower level of efficacy, the pathways for processing the simuli. In absence of awareness of space also awareness of touch or haptic recognition of objects is prevented, although not being direclty affected by the brain damage (see [79]). Further research, would clarify the alternative pathways involved in non-conscious processing.

5.3. Space and touch

Some data presented in this review clearly indicate how the conscious processing of touch is linked both to somatotopic representations in S1, therefore anchored to the limb that has been stimulated, and to spatial reference systems linked to extrapersonal space representations encoded by the posteroparietal areas [60,61]. Indeed, conscious report of tactile stimuli not only depend on the normal funcioning of the neurons in S1, but also on the space where the limb (the body) receive the stimulations. In other word, research on tactile awareness (as on neglect patients) contribute to demonsrate that space is a necessary pre-requisite for any other consious experience. Therefore, a model of tactile awareness should take into accont the, possible reciprocal, connections of S1 and S2 with the area that subserve spatial representation. This is represented in the model of Gallace and Spence [14]. In their model some of the circuits related to high order processes that modulate tactile processing are represented in a unique block of functions containing the various frame of reference in which space is computed. Dedicated studies in the future should take into account the possiblities of double dissociations between tactile awareness and specific spatial functions, in order to better specify the complex relation between skin, body and space (see for instance, [12]).

5.4. Vision and touch

Many of the studies presented in this review unequivocally indicate the modulatory effect of vision on touch when, under experimental conditions, a conflict between what the subject sees and what the subject feels is generated. It must be noted that many studies in the literature have shown the so called ‘visual enhancement of touch’ (VET) [85], that is an improved tactile acuity when a subject sees a part of the body being touched. The VET could be due to a direct connection of the visual pathways with the areas of the sensory homunculus that in S1 somatotopically represent the part of the limb that is touched. This in our view should not predict that in MBI illusion, stimuli delivered at threshold-level on the real left hand that underwent the illusion are perceived more easily following exposure to the mirror, as instead demonstrated by Ro and colleagues [40]. Indeed, the visual stimulus that creates the illusion in the mirror (i.e. the fact that the subjects sees the reflected hand been touched as if it was the left hand being touched), did not correspond to the part of the body where the enhancement in the post-illusion occurred. In other word, in this particular experiment, a VET is observed on a hand that was not stimulated. Since touch is so inextricably linked to the body surely the enhancement has to do with the particular prerogative that the body has as an object that undergoes the tactile stimulation. Importantly, the fact that vision has an effect on touch does not mean that visual consciousness dominates over tactile consciousness [13]. For instance, the experiments discussed in these review on RHI and MBI, show that although vision entrains touch, even vision per se is deceived because it basically does not distinguish between a rubber hand (as in RHI) or a mirror image of the hand (as in MBI) and a real hand. Therefore, vision affects touch but via body image. In a certain sense it is the body image that guides touch perception even when it is damaged by a brain injury (as in the various ownership disorders we have discussed) or altered by incongruent multisensory stimulation (as in RHI and MBI). This implies that vision has access to body representation and in particular to the body image that consciously represent the visual feature of our bodies.

5.5. Body representation and touch

Leaving aside the effects on touch of illusions like MBI and RHI in healthy individuals that we already discussed above, one of the most amazing evidences that touch depends on body perception is the false beliefs about tactile awareness observed in patients with body ownership problems. In these review, we took into consideration both illusion of disownership, (as in somatoparaphrenia, SPP, and body integrity disphoria, BID) and illusion of ownership (as in Patological Embidiment, PE). As we have seen, in discorporation illusions the affected limb is not only misrecognized verbally, but also treated by body representation systems as not belonging to the patient's body. This is shown incredibly convincingly when SPP patients with intact S1 (i.e., could feel touch on the discorporated hand) seem to lack tactile awareness of the contralesional stimuli (e.g., patient FB in [62]). Similarly, in BID, although the brain alteration is less pronounced than in SPP patients, tactile sensation is decreased. Consistent with the patients verbally reported conscious experience, the discorporated limb is treated by the body's alertness and defense systems as an alien limb, not belonging to the own body (see results in SCR). On the other hand, and somehow more strikingly, PE patients report a tactile sensory experience on the embodied hand. Again, the SCR is consistent with the non-veridical sensation reported by the patients, showing that in these cases the alert and defense systems treat and recognize the alien hand as belonging to the patient’s body. Surely these data again indicate that vision entrains tactile perception because in both, illusions in normal subjects and in patients' non-veridical tactile experiences, it is the vision of real and alien limbs been stimulated that produces the experience of touch. However, as already mentioned, the crucial difference between the two is that patients are convinced that a limb of their body does not belong to them (SPP and BID) or that an alien limb is part of their body. These beliefs are cognitively impenetrable and thus dependent on consistent alterations in body maps. We have already mentioned the distinction between body image and body schema. If we maintain this distinction we may say that both are affected by the alteration of body representation. On one hand to accept or refuse limbs must depend on altered body image, that is on an impairment on how we see the body. But also the body schema is affected because, for instance, we demonstrated that in PE the false beliefs about own body affect the motor parameter in the execution of action with the unaffected hand [74]. Recently we proposed a model of body ownership that building on some suggestions in previous proposal [9] try to explain the different observations in brain-injured patients. In particular we pointed to the possibility that in both disownership and PE a damage to the way in which the body is conceived can determine the patients’ behaviour. To this respect, Tsakiris and Haggard [9] proposed that the way in which we experience our body depend upon the match between bottom-up sensory information and a pre-existing body representations (PEBR) that is related to the knowledge about how bodies should be. This high order representation might be altered in patients with body ownership disorders. However, Tsakiris [55] did not distinguish between a general knowledge about bodies and a more specific knowledge about one’s own body. So we propose that there must at least two different representations which can be linked to the body image. A pre-existing body representation related to general knowledge about bodies (PEBR-G) and a pre-existing body representation related to knowledge about the own body that we call pre-existing body representation-own (PEBR-O). In the patients described in this review PEBR-G is intact. Indeed, patients know how human bodies are structured and that body part are made of biological matter. This knowledge constrains not only the RHI in healthy subjects, but also the embodiment of alien limb in PE patients (alien limb are not always incorporated, but only when they are real hand and in position compatible to the patient’s body). What is impaired in patients with body ownership disorder is the PEBR-O. Whether rejecting one's own limb or accepting someone else's limb as one's own, patients have a disturbance in recognizing their own limbs. Bottom-up multisensory stimulation that should ensure veridical processing of one's own limbs and the limbs of others does not match the PEBR-O, affected by the lesion. This distinction between general knowledge about bodies and specific knowledge about one's own body must be considered when constructing models that take tactile consciousness into account. What is interesting for the present discussion is that when PEBR-O is damaged it creates an illusion of ownership that pervades all bodily experience and affects sensory consciousnesses in a top-down manner, regardless of where stimulations are given on the body. The altered non-veridical higher-order representation of one's body wins the somatotopic representation of touch generated by skin stimulation, demonstrating once again that the integrity of S1 is not a sufficient condition to generate a veridical experience of the event that impact our body.

6. Conclusion

This review discussed how tactile consciousness can be generated from body stimulations even under illusion conditions in normal subjects and patients with brain damage and body ownership disorders. The different studies showed, albeit in different experimental situations, that it is possible to have an experience of touch even when one's own body is not stimulated and, conversely, to deny having felt touch when neural conditions allow it. Overall, the studies suggest that consciousness of events is constructed within a sensory modality (touch in this review) where primary sensory cortices interact with high order brain areas devoted to space and body awareness. The neuropsychological syndromes and the research on normal subjects described in the review suggest the existence, both cognitively and neurobiologically, of a heterogeneous structure of conscious processes, opposed to the idea of a unitary structure, and indicate how consciousness is not a function superimposed hierarchically on other cognitive activities, with a monolithic and inseparable structure, but rather a distributed property in the brain, inextricably implemented in the circuits dedicated to the various cognitive, somatosensory and motor functions.

Author contribution

Writing – Original Draft Preparation, E.C. and A.B.; Writing – Review & Editing, C.Z., R.G., H.S., R.R.; conceptualization, E.C. and A.B.; supervision, A.B. and R.R.; project administration, A.B. and R.R.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflicts of interest

References

  1. A. J. Bremner and C. Spence, “Chapter Seven - The Development of Tactile Perception,” in Advances in Child Development and Behavior, vol. 52, J. B. Benson, Ed., JAI, 2017, pp. 227–268. [CrossRef]
  2. A. Iriki, M. Tanaka, and Y. Iwamura, “Coding of modified body schema during tool use by macaque postcentral neurones,” Neuroreport, vol. 7, no. 14, pp. 2325–2330, Oct. 1996. [CrossRef]
  3. A. Sposito, N. Bolognini, G. Vallar, and A. Maravita, “Extension of perceived arm length following tool-use: Clues to plasticity of body metrics,” Neuropsychologia, vol. 50, no. 9, pp. 2187–2194, Jul. 2012. [CrossRef]
  4. M. Neppi-Mòdona et al., “Bisecting Lines with Different Tools in Right Brain Damaged Patients: The Role of Action Programming and Sensory Feedback in Modulating Spatial Remapping,” Cortex, vol. 43, no. 3, pp. 397–410, Jan. 2007. [CrossRef]
  5. D. Romano and A. Maravita, “The dynamic nature of the sense of ownership after brain injury. Clues from asomatognosia and somatoparaphrenia,” Neuropsychologia, vol. 132, p. 107119, Sep. 2019. [CrossRef]
  6. G. Tosi, A. Maravita, and D. Romano, “I am the metre: The representation of one’s body size affects the perception of tactile distances on the body,” Q. J. Exp. Psychol., vol. 75, no. 4, pp. 583–597, Apr. 2022. [CrossRef]
  7. F. de Vignemont, “Embodiment, ownership and disownership,” Conscious. Cogn., vol. 20, no. 1, pp. 82–93, Mar. 2011. [CrossRef]
  8. S. Gallagher, How the Body Shapes the Mind. Clarendon Press, 2006.
  9. M. Tsakiris and P. Haggard, “The Rubber Hand Illusion Revisited: Visuotactile Integration and Self-Attribution,” J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform., vol. 31, no. 1, pp. 80–91, 2005. [CrossRef]
  10. O. Blanke, M. Slater, and A. Serino, “Behavioral, Neural, and Computational Principles of Bodily Self-Consciousness,” Neuron, vol. 88, no. 1, pp. 145–166, Oct. 2015. [CrossRef]
  11. T. Field, “Touch for socioemotional and physical well-being: A review,” Dev. Rev., vol. 30, no. 4, pp. 367–383, Dec. 2010. [CrossRef]
  12. E. H. F. de Haan and H. C. Dijkerman, “Somatosensation in the brain: A theoretical re-evaluation and a new model,” Trends Cogn. Sci., vol. 24, no. 7, pp. 529–541, 2020. [CrossRef]
  13. A. Gallace and C. Spence, “The cognitive and neural correlates of ‘tactile consciousness’: A multisensory perspective,” Conscious. Cogn., vol. 17, no. 1, pp. 370–407, Mar. 2008. [CrossRef]
  14. A. Gallace and C. Spence, “Touch and the Body,” PSYCHE Interdiscip. J. Res. Conscious., vol. 16, no. 1, pp. 30–67, 2010.
  15. Consciousness in contemporary science. in Consciousness in contemporary science. New York, NY, US: Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press, 1988, pp. x, 405.
  16. L. Weiskrantz, Consciousness Lost and Found: A Neuropsychological Exploration. OUP Oxford, 1997.
  17. B. Libet, Mind Time: The Temporal Factor in Consciousness, vol. 19. 2004. [CrossRef]
  18. A. Berti, “Cognition in dyschiria: Edoardo Bisiach’s theory on misconception of space and consciousness,” Jan. 2004.
  19. A. Berti, Neuropsicologia della coscienza. Bollati Boringhieri, 2010. Accessed: Jun. 02, 2024. [Online]. Available: https://www.sinpia.eu/rivista/2010004/12Berti.pdf.
  20. A. Serino and P. Haggard, “Touch and the body,” Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev., vol. 34, no. 2, pp. 224–236, Feb. 2010. [CrossRef]
  21. F. Garbarini, C. Fossataro, L. Pia, and A. Berti, “What pathological embodiment/disembodiment tell us about body representations,” Neuropsychologia, vol. 149, p. 107666, Dec. 2020. [CrossRef]
  22. J. Danckert, C. Striemer, and Y. Rossetti, “Chapter 16 - Blindsight,” in Handbook of Clinical Neurology, vol. 178, J. J. S. Barton and A. Leff, Eds., in Neurology of Vision and Visual Disorders, vol. 178. , Elsevier, 2021, pp. 297–310. [CrossRef]
  23. D. Derrien, C. Garric, C. Sergent, and S. Chokron, “The nature of blindsight: implications for current theories of consciousness,” Neurosci. Conscious., vol. 2022, no. 1, p. niab043, Oct. 2022. [CrossRef]
  24. E. Pöppel, R. Held, and D. Frost, “Residual Visual Function After Brain Wounds Involving the Central Visual Pathways in Man,” Nature, vol. 243, pp. 295–6, Jul. 1973. [CrossRef]
  25. L. Weiskrantz, E. K. Warrington, M. D. Sanders, and J. Marshall, “Visual capacity in the hemianopic field following a restricted occipital ablation,” Brain J. Neurol., vol. 97, no. 4, pp. 709–728, Dec. 1974. [CrossRef]
  26. P. Stoerig and A. Cowey, “Blindsight in man and monkey,” Brain J. Neurol., vol. 120 ( Pt 3), pp. 535–559, Mar. 1997. [CrossRef]
  27. P. S. Churchland, Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind-Brain. MIT Press, 1986.
  28. F. Tomaiuolo, M. Ptito, C. Marzi, T. Paus, and A. Ptito, “Blindsight in hemispherectomized patients as revealed by spatial summation across the vertical meridian,” Brain J. Neurol., vol. 120 ( Pt 5), pp. 795–803, Jun. 1997. [CrossRef]
  29. L. Weiskrantz, J. L. Barbur, and A. Sahraie, “Parameters affecting conscious versus unconscious visual discrimination with damage to the visual cortex (V1).,” Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A., vol. 92, no. 13, pp. 6122–6126, Jun. 1995.
  30. A. Sahraie, L. Weiskrantz, J. Barbur, A. Simmons, S. Williams, and M. J. Brammer, “Sahraie, A. et al . Pattern of neuronal activity associated with conscious and unconscious processing of visual signals. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 94, 9406-9411,” Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci., vol. 94, Sep. 1997. [CrossRef]
  31. M. Tamietto et al., “Collicular vision guides nonconscious behavior,” J. Cogn. Neurosci., vol. 22, no. 5, pp. 888–902, May 2010. [CrossRef]
  32. J. Paillard, F. Michel, and G. Stelmach, “Localization without content. A tactile analogue of ‘blind sight,’” Arch. Neurol., vol. 40, no. 9, pp. 548–551, Sep. 1983. [CrossRef]
  33. Y. Rossetti, G. Rode, and D. Boisson, “Implicit processing of somaesthetic information: a dissociation between where and how?,” NeuroReport, vol. 6, no. 3, p. 506, Feb. 1995.
  34. T. Ro and L. Koenig, “Unconscious Touch Perception After Disruption of the Primary Somatosensory Cortex,” Psychol. Sci., vol. 32, no. 4, pp. 549–557, Apr. 2021. [CrossRef]
  35. J. Driver, P. Vuilleumier, M. Eimer, and G. Rees, “Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging and Evoked Potential Correlates of Conscious and Unconscious Vision in Parietal Extinction Patients,” NeuroImage, vol. 14, no. 1, pp. S68–S75, Jul. 2001. [CrossRef]
  36. G. Rees, E. Wojciulik, K. Clarke, M. Husain, C. Frith, and J. Driver, “Unconscious activation of visual cortex in the damaged right hemisphere of a parietal patient with extinction,” Brain J. Neurol., vol. 123 ( Pt 8), pp. 1624–1633, Aug. 2000. [CrossRef]
  37. J. Driver, P. Vuilleumier, and M. Husain, “Spatial Neglect and Extinction,” in The cognitive neurosciences, 3rd ed, Cambridge, MA, US: Boston Review, 2004, pp. 589–606.
  38. A. Berti and G. Rizzolatti, “Visual Processing without Awareness: Evidence from Unilateral Neglect,” J. Cogn. Neurosci., vol. 4, no. 4, pp. 345–351, Oct. 1992. [CrossRef]
  39. M. Sarri, F. Blankenburg, and J. Driver, “Neural correlates of crossmodal visual-tactile extinction and of tactile awareness revealed by fMRI in a right-hemisphere stroke patient,” Neuropsychologia, vol. 44, pp. 2398–410, Dec. 2006. [CrossRef]
  40. A. Maravita, “Implicit processing of somatosensory stimuli disclosed by a perceptual after-effect,” NeuroReport, vol. 8, no. 7, p. 1671, May 1997.
  41. A. Berti, S. Oxbury, J. Oxbury, P. Affanni, C. Umilta, and L. Orlandi, “Somatosensory extinction for meaningful objects in a patient with right hemispheric stroke,” Neuropsychologia, vol. 37, no. 3, pp. 333–343, Mar. 1999. [CrossRef]
  42. S. Aglioti, N. Smania, and A. Peru, “Frames of Reference for Mapping Tactile Stimuli in Brain-Damaged Patients,” J. Cogn. Neurosci., vol. 11, no. 1, pp. 67–79, Jan. 1999. [CrossRef]
  43. G. Von Békésy, Experiments in hearing. in Experiments in hearing. Oxford, England: Mcgraw Hill, 1960, pp. x, 745.
  44. L. M. Chen, R. M. Friedman, and A. W. Roe, “Optical imaging of a tactile illusion in area 3b of the primary somatosensory cortex,” Science, vol. 302, no. 5646, pp. 881–885, Oct. 2003. [CrossRef]
  45. F. A. Geldard and C. E. Sherrick, “The Cutaneous ‘Rabbit’: A Perceptual Illusion,” Science, vol. 178, no. 4057, pp. 178–179, Oct. 1972. [CrossRef]
  46. F. A. Geldard, “Saltation in somesthesis,” Psychol. Bull., vol. 92, no. 1, pp. 136–175, 1982. [CrossRef]
  47. M. Eimer, B. Forster, and J. Vibell, “Cutaneous saltation within and across arms: A new measure of the saltation illusion in somatosensation,” Percept. Psychophys., vol. 67, no. 3, pp. 458–468, Apr. 2005. [CrossRef]
  48. F. Blankenburg, C. C. Ruff, R. Deichmann, G. Rees, and J. Driver, “The Cutaneous Rabbit Illusion Affects Human Primary Sensory Cortex Somatotopically,” PLoS Biol., vol. 4, no. 3, p. e69, Mar. 2006. [CrossRef]
  49. M. Botvinick and J. Cohen, “Rubber hands ‘feel’ touch that eyes see,” Nature, vol. 391, no. 6669, pp. 756–756, Feb. 1998. [CrossRef]
  50. F. Pavani and M. Zampini, “The Role of Hand Size in the Fake-Hand Illusion Paradigm,” Perception, vol. 36, no. 10, pp. 1547–1554, Oct. 2007. [CrossRef]
  51. H. H. Ehrsson, N. P. Holmes, and R. E. Passingham, “Touching a Rubber Hand: Feeling of Body Ownership Is Associated with Activity in Multisensory Brain Areas,” J. Neurosci., vol. 25, no. 45, pp. 10564–10573, Nov. 2005. [CrossRef]
  52. D. Zeller, V. Litvak, K. J. Friston, and J. Classen, “Sensory Processing and the Rubber Hand Illusion—An Evoked Potentials Study,” J. Cogn. Neurosci., vol. 27, pp. 573–582, 2015. [CrossRef]
  53. F. della Gatta, F. Garbarini, G. Puglisi, A. Leonetti, A. Berti, and P. Borroni, “Decreased motor cortex excitability mirrors own hand disembodiment during the rubber hand illusion,” eLife, vol. 5, p. e14972, Oct. 2016. [CrossRef]
  54. H. H. Ehrsson, C. Spence, and R. E. Passingham, “That’s My Hand! Activity in Premotor Cortex Reflects Feeling of Ownership of a Limb,” Science, vol. 305, no. 5685, pp. 875–877, Aug. 2004. [CrossRef]
  55. G. Rizzolatti, C. Scandolara, M. Matelli, and M. Gentilucci, “Afferent properties of periarcuate neurons in macaque monkeys. II. Visual responses,” Behav. Brain Res., vol. 2, no. 2, pp. 147–163, Mar. 1981. [CrossRef]
  56. M. S. A. Graziano, X. T. Hu, and C. G. Gross, “Visuospatial Properties of Ventral Premotor Cortex,” J. Neurophysiol., vol. 77, no. 5, pp. 2268–2292, May 1997. [CrossRef]
  57. M. Schaefer, H. Flor, H.-J. Heinze, and M. Rotte, “Morphing the body: Illusory feeling of an elongated arm affects somatosensory homunculus,” NeuroImage, vol. 36, no. 3, pp. 700–705, Jul. 2007. [CrossRef]
  58. V. S. Ramachandran, D. Rogers-Ramachandran, and S. Cobb, “Touching the phantom limb,” Nature, vol. 377, no. 6549, pp. 489–490, Oct. 1995. [CrossRef]
  59. V. S. Ramachandran and W. Hirstein, “The perception of phantom limbs. The D. O. Hebb lecture.,” Brain, vol. 121, no. 9, pp. 1603–1630, Sep. 1998. [CrossRef]
  60. V. S. Ramachandran and D. Rogers-Ramachandran, “Synaesthesia in phantom limbs induced with mirrors,” Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci., vol. 263, no. 1369, pp. 377–386, Jan. 1997. [CrossRef]
  61. T. Ro, R. Wallace, J. Hagedorn, A. Farné, and E. Pienkos, “Visual Enhancing of Tactile Perception in the Posterior Parietal Cortex,” J. Cogn. Neurosci., vol. 16, no. 1, pp. 24–30, 2004. [CrossRef]
  62. J. P. Hunter, J. Katz, and K. D. Davis, “The effect of tactile and visual sensory inputs on phantom limb awareness,” Brain, vol. 126, no. 3, pp. 579–589, Mar. 2003. [CrossRef]
  63. R. B. Welch and D. H. Warren, “Immediate perceptual response to intersensory discrepancy,” Psychol. Bull., vol. 88, no. 3, pp. 638–667, 1980. [CrossRef]
  64. L. L. Egsgaard, L. Petrini, G. Christoffersen, and L. Arendt-Nielsen, “Cortical responses to the mirror box illusion: a high-resolution EEG study,” Exp. Brain Res., vol. 215, no. 3, pp. 345–357, Dec. 2011. [CrossRef]
  65. R. Ricci et al., “When Right Goes Left: Phantom Touch Induced by Mirror Box Procedure in Healthy Individuals,” Front. Hum. Neurosci., vol. 15, p. 734235, 2021. [CrossRef]
  66. J. Medina and B. Rapp, “Phantom Tactile Sensations Modulated by Body Position,” vol. 18, no. 24, 2008.
  67. J. Medina and H. B. Coslett, “What can errors tell us about body representations?,” Cogn. Neuropsychol., vol. 33, no. 1–2, pp. 5–25, 2016. [CrossRef]
  68. R. Ricci et al., “Effects of attentional and cognitive variables on unilateral spatial neglect,” Neuropsychologia, vol. 92, pp. 158–166, Nov. 2016. [CrossRef]
  69. E. Bisiach, “Unilateral Neglect and Related Disorders,” in Handbook Of Clinical And Experimental Neuropsychology, Psychology Press, 1998.
  70. H. OBERSTEINER, “ON ALLOCHIRIA: A PECULIAR SENSORY DISORDER,” Brain, vol. 4, no. 2, pp. 153–163, Jul. 1881. [CrossRef]
  71. R. Ricci et al., “Phantom touch: How to unmask sensory unawareness after stroke,” Cortex, vol. 121, pp. 253–263, Dec. 2019. [CrossRef]
  72. S. Noachtar, H. O. Lüders, D. S. Dinner, and G. Klem, “Ipsilateral median somatosensory evoked potentials recorded from human somatosensory cortex,” Electroencephalogr. Clin. Neurophysiol., vol. 104, no. 3, pp. 189–198, May 1997. [CrossRef]
  73. T. Hansson and T. Brismar, “Tactile stimulation of the hand causes bilateral cortical activation: a functional magnetic resonance study in humans,” Neurosci. Lett., vol. 271, no. 1, pp. 29–32, Aug. 1999. [CrossRef]
  74. L. Tamè et al., “The contribution of primary and secondary somatosensory cortices to the representation of body parts and body sides: an fMRI adaptation study,” J. Cogn. Neurosci., vol. 24, no. 12, pp. 2306–2320, Dec. 2012. [CrossRef]
  75. L. Tamè, C. Braun, N. P. Holmes, A. Farnè, and F. Pavani, “Bilateral representations of touch in the primary somatosensory cortex,” Cogn. Neuropsychol., vol. 33, no. 1–2, pp. 48–66, 2016. [CrossRef]
  76. M. Tsakiris, “The multisensory basis of the self: From body to identity to others,” Q. J. Exp. Psychol., vol. 70, no. 4, pp. 597–609, Apr. 2017. [CrossRef]
  77. H. HEAD and G. HOLMES, “SENSORY DISTURBANCES FROM CEREBRAL LESIONS1,” Brain, vol. 34, no. 2–3, pp. 102–254, Nov. 1911. [CrossRef]
  78. G. Berlucchi and S. Aglioti, “The body in the brain: neural bases of corporeal awareness,” Trends Neurosci., vol. 20, no. 12, pp. 560–564, Dec. 1997. [CrossRef]
  79. G. Berlucchi and S. M. Aglioti, “The body in the brain revisited,” Exp. Brain Res., vol. 200, no. 1, pp. 25–35, Jan. 2010. [CrossRef]
  80. J. Gerstmann, “PSYCHOLOGICAL AND PHENOMENOLOGICAL ASPECTS OF DISORDERS OF THE BODY IMAGE,” J. Nerv. Ment. Dis., vol. 126, no. 6, p. 499, Jun. 1958.
  81. V. Moro, M. Zampini, and S. M. Aglioti, “Changes in Spatial Position of Hands Modify Tactile Extinction but not Disownership of Contralesional Hand in Two Right Brain-Damaged Patients,” Neurocase, vol. 10, no. 6, pp. 437–443, Dec. 2004. [CrossRef]
  82. G. Bottini, E. Bisiach, R. Sterzi, and G. Vallar, “Feeling Touches in Someone Else’s Hand,” Neuroreport, vol. 13, pp. 249–52, Mar. 2002. [CrossRef]
  83. D. Romano, C. Pfeiffer, A. Maravita, and O. Blanke, “Illusory self-identification with an avatar reduces arousal responses to painful stimuli,” Behav. Brain Res., vol. 261, pp. 275–281, Mar. 2014. [CrossRef]
  84. L. M. Hilti et al., “The desire for healthy limb amputation: structural brain correlates and clinical features of xenomelia,” Brain, vol. 136, no. 1, pp. 318–329, Jan. 2013. [CrossRef]
  85. P. D. McGeoch, D. Brang, T. Song, R. R. Lee, M. Huang, and V. S. Ramachandran, “Xenomelia: a new right parietal lobe syndrome,” J. Neurol. Neurosurg. Psychiatry, vol. 82, no. 12, pp. 1314–1319, Dec. 2011. [CrossRef]
  86. A. Berti and F. Garbarini, “L’uomo con tre mani. storie di corpi e identità,” 2019, Accessed: May 29, 2024. [Online]. Available: https://www.torrossa.com/it/resources/an/5704647.
  87. M. B. First, “Desire for amputation of a limb: paraphilia, psychosis, or a new type of identity disorder,” Psychol. Med., vol. 35, no. 6, pp. 919–928, Jun. 2005. [CrossRef]
  88. D. Romano, A. Sedda, P. Brugger, and G. Bottini, “Body ownership: When feeling and knowing diverge,” Conscious. Cogn., vol. 34, pp. 140–148, Jul. 2015. [CrossRef]
  89. D. Brang, P. D. McGeoch, and V. S. Ramachandran, “Apotemnophilia: a neurological disorder,” NeuroReport, vol. 19, no. 13, p. 1305, Aug. 2008. [CrossRef]
  90. G. Saetta et al., “Neural Correlates of Body Integrity Dysphoria,” Curr. Biol., vol. 30, no. 11, pp. 2191-2195.e3, Jun. 2020. [CrossRef]
  91. M. Gandola et al., “An anatomical account of somatoparaphrenia,” Cortex, vol. 48, no. 9, pp. 1165–1178, Oct. 2012. [CrossRef]
  92. H.-O. Karnath and B. Baier, “Right insula for our sense of limb ownership and self-awareness of actions,” Brain Struct. Funct., vol. 214, no. 5, pp. 411–417, Jun. 2010. [CrossRef]
  93. L. Pia et al., “The anatomo-clinical picture of the pathological embodiment over someone else’s body part after stroke,” Cortex, vol. 130, pp. 203–219, Sep. 2020. [CrossRef]
  94. F. Garbarini, A. Piedimonte, M. Dotta, L. Pia, and A. Berti, “Dissociations and similarities in motor intention and motor awareness: the case of anosognosia for hemiplegia and motor neglect,” J. Neurol. Neurosurg. Psychiatry, vol. 84, no. 4, pp. 416–419, Apr. 2013. [CrossRef]
  95. F. Garbarini et al., “When your arm becomes mine: Pathological embodiment of alien limbs using tools modulates own body representation,” Neuropsychologia, vol. 70, pp. 402–413, Apr. 2015. [CrossRef]
  96. L. Pia, F. Garbarini, C. Fossataro, L. Fornia, and A. M. Berti, “Pain and Body Awareness: Evidence from Brain-Damaged Patients with Delusional Body Ownership,” Front. Hum. Neurosci., vol. 7, Jun. 2013. [CrossRef]
  97. F. Garbarini, L. Fornia, C. Fossataro, L. Pia, P. Gindri, and A. Berti, “Embodiment of others’ hands elicits arousal responses similar to one’s own hands,” Curr. Biol., vol. 24, no. 16, pp. R738–R739, Aug. 2014. [CrossRef]
  98. E. I. Kandel, Functional and Stereotactic Neurosurgery. Springer Science & Business Media, 2012.
  99. A. Berti et al., “Shared Cortical Anatomy for Motor Awareness and Motor Control,” Science, vol. 309, no. 5733, pp. 488–491, Jul. 2005. [CrossRef]
  100. M. Longo, S. Cardozo, and P. Haggard, “Visual enhancement of touch and bodily self,” Conscious. Cogn., vol. 17, pp. 1181–1191, Dec. 2008. [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.
Copyright: This open access article is published under a Creative Commons CC BY 4.0 license, which permit the free download, distribution, and reuse, provided that the author and preprint are cited in any reuse.

Downloads

123

Views

74

Comments

0

Subscription

Notify me about updates to this article or when a peer-reviewed version is published.

Email

Prerpints.org logo

Preprints.org is a free preprint server supported by MDPI in Basel, Switzerland.

Subscribe

© 2025 MDPI (Basel, Switzerland) unless otherwise stated