1. Introduction and Preliminaries
Let
S be a monoid. By a right
S-act we mean a non-empty set
A together with an action
given by
such that for all
and
We refer the reader to [
1,
7,
9] for all undefined terms concerning acts over monoids.
Mahmoudi and Renshaw introduced coessential epimorphisms and covers of cyclic
S-acts in [
9], gave a description of coessential epimorphisms in terms of congruence classes and a method of constructing covers from left unitary submonoids, and defined a strongly flat cover, Condition
cover, projective cover and provided a necessary and sufficient condition for a cyclic
S-act to have a strongly flat cover, Condition
cover and projective cover. Now we restrict our attention to these notions.
Let
S be a monoid. A right
S-act
B is called a cover of a right
S-act
A if there exists an epimorphism
such that for any proper subact
C of
B the restriction
is not an epimorphism. Moreover, we call an
S-epimorphism
coessential in [
9] if for each
S-act
C and each
S-map
, if
is an epimorphism, then
g is an epimorphism. And we shall say that an act
B together with an
S-epimorphism
is a
X-cover of
A if
B satisfies property
X and
f is coessential. It is easy to see that
is a cover of
A if and only if it is a coessential epimorphism. Let
be a class of right
S-acts. We assume that
is closed under isomorphisms, i.e., if
and
, then
.
The concept of cover used in [
5] is slightly different from that given above. (Enochs’ notion) For a right
S-act
A, an
S-act
is called an
-cover of
A if there is a homomorphism
such that
(1) for any homomorphism
:
with
, there is a homomorphism
f:
with
. In other words, the following diagram

commutes;
(2) If an endomorphism is such that , then f must be an automorphism.
If (1) holds, we call : an -precover.
Recall that an S-act is called strongly flat if the tensor functor preserves pullbacks and equalizers. An S-act is said to satisfy Condition if for all such that , then there exist with and . And recall that an S-act satisfies Condition if for , implies that there exist such that and . It is well known that an act A is strongly flat if and only if it satisfies Condition and Condition . We are principally concerned with finitely generated S-acts here and with the concepts of strongly flatness and Condition and in these cases there are useful characterizations.
A monoid S is called right reversible if for all , there exist such that . A monoid S is called left collapsible if for all , there exists such that . A submonoid T of S is said to be left unitary if and only if whenever then .
Throughout this paper, S denotes a monoid, is said that A is a n-generated right S-act and . And will denote a coproduct of cyclic subacts for all . We shall deal exclusively with right S-acts and simply refer to them as S-acts. We shall also consistently write our maps on the left so that means f followed by g.
The main results here are descriptions of finitely generated acts and coproducts in
Section 2, and we provide a necessary and sufficient condition for a finitely generated
S-act to have a cover in
Section 3. Next in
Section 4 we concentrate on strongly flat covers, Condition
covers and projective covers, and the main conclusions extend some known results in [
9]. In
Section 5 we study Enochs’ notion of cover in the category of acts over monoids and focus on
-precovers, where
is a class of
S-acts closed under isomorphisms. Basic results on covers of acts over monoids can be found in [
3,
4,
6,
11].
2. Finite Generation and Coproducts
This section aims to describe the finite generation and coproduct of
S-acts. A subset
U of an
S-act
A is a generating set for
A if for any
, there exist
,
such that
. In other words,
U is a set of generating elements for
if
, where
. An
S-act
A is said to be finitely generated (resp. cyclic) if it has a finite (resp. one-element) generating set. Further details may be found, for example, in [
7].
Proposition 2.1. Let S be a monoid and be S-act, is a subact of A. For every , is finitely generated, then A is finitely generated.
Proof. Let . Then . □
Proposition 2.2. Let S be a monoid and an S-act, are subacts of A for . And for , suppose that is either finitely generated or empty. If A is finitely generated, then for all , is finitely generated.
Proof. Let
, it is clear by Lemma 5.3 of [
10]. If
the assertion is hold, that is, for
,
is either finitely generated or empty, if
A is finitely generated, then
, is finitely generated. Assume that
. If
,
, obviously. Otherwise, take
, for
,
is finitely generated, by Proposition 2.1,
is finitely generated. Since
is finitely generated,
and
are finitely generated. By assumption,
,
, is finitely generated. Therefore, for all
,
is finitely generated. □
Corollary 2.1. Let S be a monoid. S-act is finitely generated if and only if S-act is finitely generated.
It is important for monoids to consider the covers of finitely generated acts. Now we first aim to investigate the cover of coproducts of acts.
Proposition 2.3. Suppose that are a family of S-morphisms, where . Let , , and satisfies . Then is a cover of A if and only if are covers of for all .
Proof. Sufficiency. Since , are a family of epimorphisms, it is clear that is epimorphic. Assume that f is not coessential, that is, there exists a proper subact of B such that is epimorphic. Therefore, there is such that is a proper subact of . Thus, is not epimorphism since is a coessential epimorphism, so there exists such that for all . However, by the surjectivity of , we obtain that for some . Thus there exists such that , . Then which contradicts .
Necessity. Let be a coessential epimorphism. Then we obtain that are a family of epimorphisms for all . To show that are coessential for all , assume that there exists a map such that is not coessential, where . Then is an epimorphism for some proper subact of . Thus is an epimorphism. But is a proper subact of and by assumption is not epimorphic, a contradiction. So are a family of coessential epimorphisms for all . □
Now we concentrate on covers of finitely generated of S-acts and we begin with some notations. For an element a of a right S-act A we denote by the set , the submonoid of right identities of a, and it is clear that is a left unitary submonoid of S. We denote by the set . In particular, , the right annihilator congruence of a. It is clear that is isomorphic to under the S-isomorphism , where denote the class of with respect to an equivalence relation .
Lemma 2.1 ([
7], Proporsition III.13.14).
Let be a finitely generated S-act. If satisfies Condition , then is a coproduct of cyclic subacts.
Let S be a monoid and , where are right S-acts. Then A is strongly flat (resp. satisfies Condition ) if and only if is strongly flat (resp. satisfies Condition ) for every . The following results turn out very helpful in the following section.
Proposition 2.4. If the finitely generated S-act is strongly flat(resp. satisfis Conditon (P)), then is a left collapsible(resp. right reversible) submonoid of S.
Proof. Let A satisfy Conditon . By Lemma 2.1, satisfies Conditon for . Thus is right reversible. And in a similar way we obtain that is a left collapsible submonoid of S if A is strongly flat. □
Proposition 2.5. Let T be a submonoid of a monoid S and A a right S-act, . If , then .
Proof. Since , for any and , then . Thus , that is, . Therefore . It is clear that . □
Lemma 2.2. Let S be a monoid and P a left collapsible(resp. right reversible) submonoid of S, is n-generated. If , then is left collapsible(resp. right reversible) and is strongly flat(resp. satisfies Condition (P)).
Proof. Since , by Proposition 2.5 and so is left collapsible(resp. right reversible). Notice that in either case, P is right reversible and so defined by if and only if there exists with . Notice that . In fact, if then there exist with and so . Conversely, if , then there are with and from . So and hence . It is clear that satisfies Condition . Then satisfies Condition . If in addition P is left collapsible, then is strongly flat. □
It is clear that any cover of a cyclic right
S-act is cyclic by Lemma 2.3 of [
9]. The following theorem concerns the covers of
n-generated right
S-acts.
Theorem 2.1. Let be a cover of . Then is n-generated if and only if is n-generated.
Proof. Necessity. Assume that B is n-generated, is a generating set of B. Since is an epimorphism, A is generated by n elements. Now we are ready to prove n is the smallest. Suppose that , . Then , . Therefore , which contradicts that B is n-generated. Thus, A is n-generated.
Sufficiency. Suppose . Since f is an epimorphism, there exists such that Take , clearly and . By the definition of cover, we have . Therefore B is generated by n elements. Now we are ready to prove a result that n is the smallest. If , and , we have A is generated by , a contradiction. □
Let be n-generated and . The following Proposition 2.6 shows that is a cover of A implies that , are a family of covers of .
Proposition 2.6. Let . Let , be a family of S-morphisms, and satisfies . Then is a cover of A implies , are a family of covers of .
Proof. If for any , it is clear by Proposition 2.3. Otherwise, suppose . Since f is an epimorphism, for , there exists such that . If , we have for some . But , a contradiction. Therefore , we obtain that . By Proposition 2.3, is a cover of A implies that are covers of . □
Coversely, if B is n-generated and A is a disjoint union of n subacts, the argument always holds in Proposition 2.7.
Proposition 2.7. Suppose that , , , are a family of S-morphisms, and satisfies . Then is a cover of A if and only if are a family of covers of for every .
Proof. Let be a cover of A. If there exist such that , that is, , where , then is an epimorphism, a contradiction. So f is one-to-one. Assume . Then , and which contradicts . Hence or the element in has no image under the action of f. If the latter, then is an epimorphism, a contradiction. Therefore, . Conversely, let be a family of covers of , we obtain the same result . By Proposition 2.3, is a cover of A if and only if are a family of covers of . □
Remark 2.1. From the above several propositions it is shown that if A and B are the union(coproduct) of nS-acts and , respectively, then is a cover of A if and only if are a family of covers of for .
Let S be a monoid and X an S-act. We say that X is Noetherian if every congruence on X is finitely generated, and we say that a monoid S is Noetherian if it is Noetherian as an S-act over itself.
Proposition 2.8. Let S be a Noetherian monoid and be a cover. Then A is Noetherian if and only if B is Noetherian.
Proof. Let
be a cover of
A. If
B is Noetherian. By Lemma 7.6 of [
2], then
B is finitely generated, and so is
A by Theorem 2.1. All finitely generated
S-acts over a Noetherian monoid are Noetherian, thus
A is Noetherian. Coversely, it is obvious. □
3. Covers of Finitely Generated Acts
Let
S be a monoid and
right congruences on
S. In Mahmoudi and Renshaw [
9], it is proved that a cyclic act
has a cover
if and only if
and for all
,
. The next there propositions are needed to get the result.
Proposition 3.1. Let S be a monoid. Then is isomorphic to a finitely generated subact of if and only if there exist , such that for any .
Proof. Let be an S-monomorphism and . For , there is such that , . Since f is a monomorphism, then . Thus, we have for some and . And so for any . Let , . Then . In addition, suppose that , and we have since f is monomorphic. Therefore .
Conversely, the mapping defined by is well-defined and f is an S-monomorphism. □
Lemma 3.1. Let S be a monoid and . Consider the S-monomorphism given by , . Then f is onto if and only if for every .
Proof. Since f is an S-epimorphism. For any , there exist and such that . And since , it follows that , namely , a contradiction. Thus and so , hence .
Conversely, since , there exists such that for every . So . It is easy to see that f is an epimorphism. □
Lemma 3.2. Let S be a monoid, and . If is a coessential epimorphism then there exists such that , , is isomorphic, where . And given by is a coessential S-epimorphism. In particular, .
Proof. Since is a coessential epimorphism, it follows that A and B are n-generated. For any , there exist and such that . Suppose that given by is a monomorphism whose composite with f is clearly onto. Since B is a cover of A, and so , , is a coessential S-epimorphism. It then follows that . □
We now present a fundamental theorem that yields the main result of this section.
Theorem 3.1. Let S be a monoid and a n-generated S-act. The map given by is a coessential epimorphism if and only if , , and for all , .
Proof. Let for , and . Then because f is well-defined. Hence . For , there exist and such that , but , we obtain , a contradiction. Therefore and so . Since is a coessential epimorphism, by Lemma 3.2, there is a subact such that and is a coessential epimorphism. So we have for some . And since is isomorphic by Lemma 3.2, it follows that , thus as required.
Conversely, if the given conditions hold, then clearly f is well-defined. Let B be an S-subact of and suppose that is onto. Then for , there exists such that and we obtain , so . However , and hence . By assumption, there exists such that , in the sense that for an arbitrary . So , that is, , and f is a cover. □
If
, we can easily obtain the Theorem 2.7 in [
9].
Theorem 3.2. Let S be a monoid and a n-generated S-act. If the natural map is a coessential epimorphism, where . Then , is a subgroup of S.
Proof. Since is a coessential epimorphism. Then for an arbitrary element , . And . We can verify that for . Moreover, , it is easy to see that and so . Consequently, is a subgroup of S. □
Proposition 3.2. Let S be a monoid. Then the map is a coessential epimorphism, where , if and only if , is a subgroup of S and for .
Proof. Let , , be a coessential epimorphism. Let for and . We have since f is well-defined. By Theorem 3.2, is a subgroup of S.
Conversely, suppose that is a subgroup of S. For any , there exists such that . Thus . In addition, since for , we can verify that f is a coessential epimorphism by Theorem 3.1. □
Proposition 3.3. Let S be a right simple semigroup with a 1 adjoined and , . If for and . Then given by is a coessential epimorphism.
Proof. Since , we can verify that , where T is a right simple semigroup. So for every . Then for , . It is easy to see that f is a coessential epimorphism since . □
Remark 3.1. It follows from the above that covers of finitely generated S-acts need not be unique. If S is a group then every n-generated S-act has as a cover, where . And so proper n-generated S-acts do not have unique covers. In fact, if the map is onto, then is trivially a cover of .
4. -Generated Flat Covers
In Mahmoudi and Renshaw [
9] it is proved that an equivalent characterization of a cyclic act having flat properties covers, such as strongly flat, Condition
, projective. The next theorems are to investigate flatness covers of
n-generated
S-acts.
Theorem 4.1. Let S be a monoid. Then the n-generated S-act has a strongly flat cover B if and only if and contains a left collapsible submonoid R such that for all , .
Proof. Suppose that A has a strongly flat cover B. By Theorem 2.1, . Then by Theorem 3.1 we can assume that and that for all , . Moreover, since B is strongly flat, by Lemma 2.1 and R is left collapsible by Proposition 2.4.
Conversely, suppose that and R is a left collapsible submonoid of such that for all , . Define , then and further is strongly flat by Lemma 2.2. Define a map given by and note that f is a well-defined S-epimorphism. To see this, first notice that if f is well-defined, then it is clearly an S-map which is onto. Since , it is easy to see that but and hence . And for any , is not necessary to consider because . Further, for all , so f is coessential by Theorem 3.1. □
We can easily obtain the Theorem 3.2 of [
9] if
in Theorem 4.1.
Example 4.1. Let S be a left cancellative monoid. Then n-generated S-act has a strongly flat cover if and only if , , is a subgroup of S and in this case is a strongly flat cover of A, where . First notice that the only strongly flat cover of a n-generated S-act(assuming that it has one) is then . Notice also that not all finitely generated S-acts need have a strongly flat cover(see, for example, Remark 3.6 in [9]).
Theorem 4.2. Let S be a monoid. Then the n-generated S-act has a -cover B if and only if and contains a right reversible submonoid R such that for all , .
Proof. Suppose that A has a -cover, . Then by Theorem 3.1 we can assume that and that for all , . Moreover, since B satisfies Condition , by Lemma 2.1 and R is right reversible by Proposition 2.4.
Conversely, suppose that and R is a right reversible submonoid of such that for all , . Define , then and further satisfies Condition by Lemma 2.2. Define a map given by and note that f is a well-defined S-epimorphism. Since , it follows that but and hence . And for any , is not necessary to consider because . Further, since for all , , then f is coessential by Theorem 3.1. □
Similarly, if
, we can easily obtain the Theorem 4.2 of [
9].
Proposition 4.1. Let S be a group. Then every n-generated S-act has at least two -covers but only has a unique strongly flat cover.
Proof. Let . Since S is a group, then all S-acts satisfy condition and so in particular A is a -cover of itself. But , is a subgroup of S, thus is a cover of A by Proposition 3.2, where . While the latter part follows immediately from the Example 4.1. □
Lemma 4.1 ([
8], Corollary 3.8).
A right S-act is projective if and only if where for idempotents , .
Theorem 4.3. Let S be a monoid and a n-generated S-act. Then the following are equivalent:
A has a projective cover;
There exits a submonoid R of which has a left zero element and for all , .
The submonoid of S has a minimal right ideal generated by an idempotent.
Proof. (1)⇒(2) Let be a projective cover of A. Then by Theorem 3.1, take , for all , . Moreover by Lemma 4.1 there exists with and thus obviously and . If , then and so is a left zero element of .
(2)⇒(3) Assume that is a left zero element of R and consider the right ideal of . If this is not minimal, then there exists with . By assumption there exists with , and since is a left unitary submonoid, then . Since z is a left zero element of R, and so , which is a contradiction. Therefore the submonoid of is a minimal right ideal generated by an idempotent.
(3)⇒(1) Suppose that with is a minimal right ideal of . Clearly is projective. Define the map by . Then f is well defined since if , and , then and . In addition, it is also coessential since if , then by the minimality of , and so for some . But then and so . Hence the result follows by Theorem 3.1. □
If
in Theorem 4.3, we can get the Theorem 5.2 in [
9].
5. -Precovers
In this section we study Enochs’ notion of cover [
1] in the category of acts over monoids and focus on
-precovers and
-covers, where
will be a class of
S-acts closed under isomorphisms. For example, we denote the class of all projective
S-acts by
. Clearly the concept of cover by Enochs’ is slightly different from that the coessential cover.
Proposition 5.1. Let S be a monoid and let satisfy the property that for -act-S. If A has an -precover, then has an -precover.
Proof. Let be -precover of A. Define to be the obvious induced map. Let and let . Now, by the hypothesis, , so, since C is an -precover of A, there exists Hom such that . So define to be the induced map, and clearly . Thus, has an -precover. □
Proposition 5.2. Let A be an S-act and a class of S-acts. Any retract of any act satisfying satisfies . Then the -precover of A, if it exists, is the -precover of the retract of A.
Proof. Please see the following diagram
Let be the -precover and B the retract of A. Then and satisfy . For S-map , , by the -precover property, there exists an S-map such that . We claim that Hence, is the -precover of B. □
Proposition 5.3.
Let be a class of acts and . Consider the following commutative diagram of S-acts:
If is an -precover of S-act A, then is also a -precover of A.
Proof. Let be an S-homomorphism for . By the -precover property, there exists an S-map such that . Hence, from . So is a -precover of A. □
Theorem 5.1.
Let be a class of S-acts and be a monomorphism. Consider the following commutative diagram of S-acts:
If is an -precover of B, then is an -precover of A.
Proof. For every S-map , where . Since is an -precover of B, there exists an S-map with . Then since f is a monomorphism, and we are done. □
Dually, if is an S-epimorphism, we obtain the following Theorem 5.2.
Theorem 5.2.
Let S be a monoid and the class of all projective S-acts. Let be an S-epimorphism. Consider the following commutative diagram of S-acts:
If is a -precover of A, then is a -precover of B.
Proof. Let be -precover of A and an S-epimorphism. To show that is a -precover of B, we assume that any S-map , where . By assumption, there exists such that . Since is a -precover of A, we obtain that for some . So . Therefore, is a -precover of B. □
Remark 5.1. It is clear that if is an -cover of A, then is an -cover of B in Theorem 5.2. A question that could be brought up is whether Theorem 5.2 is valid for free S-acts. It is easy to answer this question positively.
Theorem 5.3. Let S be a monoid and a class of S-acts. If is an -precover of B and is an -precover of A. Then C is an -precover of B.
Proof. Suppose that is an -precover of B and is an -precover of A. For any S-map , for , there is an S-map with since is an -precover of B. Similarly, because is an -precover of A, we have for some S-map . Thus, we can verify that . So is an -precover of B, that is, C is an -precover of B. □
Proposition 5.4. Let S be a monoid and B a right S-act. Let be a class of S-acts closed under factor acts. If is a -precover for B, then is a -precover for B, where is a congruence on A.
Proof. Let be a congruence on A contained in and . First note that . By Homomorphism Theorem for acts, there exists a homomorphism , defined by , with , where . For each morphism with , there exists a morphism such that . Thus , that is, is a -precover for B. □
Proposition 5.5. Let be a class of S-acts which is closed under subacts. And suppose that all subacts of B have -covers. If and is an -precover and C is a proper subact of B. Then there exists an S-subact of A and a homomorphism such that it is an -cover of C.
Proof. By assumption, we note that
. Thus
is an
-precover of
C. Let
be an
-cover of
C. Then we have the commutative diagram

such that
and
, and so
. Since
h is an
-cover of
C, it follows that
is an automorphism of
. Thus
is monomorphism. Take
is an
S-subact of
A, then
is an
-cover of
C. □